Page 2 of 6

Questioning Julio Cabrera’s Questionnaire – Part 2 – Nonhuman Animals

 

The following text is the second part of my comments on some of Julio Cabrera’s replies to questions he was asked in The Exploring Antinatalism Podcast #19 – Julio Cabrera ‘Questionaire on Antinatalism’. In this part I’ll address Cabrera’s replies to questions regarding: The moral status of animals, Abortion, EFILism, and Veganism.
For comments on his replies to questions regarding his general approach to Antinatalism please read part 1. And for comments on his replies to the question of involuntary sterilization please read part 3.

Question 18:

“It is true that your philosophical and ethical beliefs are unique but there are some unique principles you promote (such as the injunction against manipulation) that intuitively apply to animals as well. Do animals deserve any consideration in a Negative Ethics framework?
Can animals be harmed in similar way as you describe people can: the moral impediment, discomforts? What moral obligations or duties (for us, humans) follow from this?”

Cabrera:

“In my philosophy the animal issue is a less important point.”

“I actually start from an abyss between human and non-human animals. Here I followed two masters of the human condition, Schopenhauer and Heidegger.”

“In terms of my philosophy, the abysmal difference between human and nonhuman is already expressed in moral terms: nonhuman animals have no moral impediment. They are not open to the domain of morality; therefore, they cannot fail to be moral as human fail, they cannot be disabled for something in which they have never been enabled. This is sufficient to understand that we cannot have ethical-negative relationships with nonhuman animals; there can be no ethical relations between beings with moral impediment and beings without it. Therefore, there can be no “incorporation of animals into the moral community” in negative ethics.

However, in this ethics morality has two basic requirements, not to manipulate and not to harm. Although there is no reciprocity between human and nonhuman animals, we can say that we manipulate and harm nonhuman animals when we treat them badly, when we hunt and eat them, because they – at their own level – feel pain, fear, want to continue living, live comfortably, etc. but strictly speaking, we cannot say that we have moral relations with them; we can only be moral about them asymmetrically, but not together with them.

In Spanish and Portuguese there is a triad of similar terms that does not exist English, and that allows me to describe my attitude towards animals: trato, contracto, maltrato, treatment, contract and mistreatment.
We can only have contracts with other humans, because a contract requires moral (or immoral) interaction. But this must not lead to mistreatment. It is incorrect and disgusting to make animals suffer or kill for fun, but it is not “immoral”, because morality requires reciprocity; it cause us discomfort to see animals suffer, but not all discomfort is a moral discomfort. If we cannot have contracts with nonhuman animals, and we don’t want to mistreat them either, we must find some kind of treatment with them, which consists of not harming them and benefiting them if possible.”

Since sentience is the only relevant criterion for moral consideration, anyone who is capable of experiencing suffering should be included within the moral community. And since harms to sentient nonhuman animals matter to them as much as harms to humans matter to humans, sentient nonhuman animals matter morally no less than humans matter morally.
To exclude sentient nonhuman animals despite their possession of the only morally relevant criterion can only be merely due to their species, and that is Speciesism – a form of prejudice based upon morally irrelevant differences, which is no more justifiable than racism or sexism.

In the words of Richard Ryder, the psychologist who coined the term in 1970:

“All animal species can suffer pain and distress. Nonhuman animals scream and writhe like us; their nervous systems are similar and contain the same biochemicals that we know are associated with the experience of pain in ourselves. So our concern for the pain and distress of others should be extended to any ‘painient’ (i.e. pain-feeling) individual regardless of his or her sex, class, race, religion, nationality or species.” (Speciesism, Painism and Happiness Page 130)

The fact that it is morally wrong to exclude a group on the basis of an arbitrary criterion is Ethics 101.

Cabrera’s claims were long ago refuted by Jeremy Bentham, as well as many others, especially Peter Singer. The following passage is taken from Animal Liberation and combines both of them:

“Many philosophers and other writers have proposed the principle of equal consideration of interests, in some form or other, as a basic moral principle; but not many of them have recognized that this principle applies to members of other species as well as to our own. Jeremy Bentham was one of the few who did realize this. In a forward-looking passage written at a time when black slaves had been freed by the French but in the British dominions were still being treated in the way we now treat animals, Bentham wrote:

The day may come when the rest of the animal creation may acquire those rights which never could have been withholden from them but by the hand of tyranny. The French have already discovered that the blackness of the skin is no reason why a human being should be abandoned without redress to the caprice of a tormentor. It may one day come to be recognized that the number of the legs, the villosity of the skin, or the termination of the os sacrum are reasons equally insufficient for abandoning a sensitive being to the same fate. What else is it that should trace the insuperable line? Is it the faculty of reason, or perhaps the faculty of discourse? But a full-grown horse or dog is beyond comparison a more rational, as well as a more conversable animal, than an infant of a day or a week or even a month, old. But suppose they were otherwise, what would it avail? The question is not, Can they reason? nor Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?

In this passage Bentham points to the capacity for suffering as the vital characteristic that gives a being the right to equal consideration. The capacity for suffering-or more strictly, for suffering and/or enjoyment or happiness-is not just another characteristic like the capacity for language or higher mathematics. Bentham is not saying that those who try to mark “the insuperable line” that determines whether the interests of a being should be considered happen to have chosen the wrong characteristic. By saying that we must consider the interests of all beings with the capacity for suffering or enjoyment Bentham does not arbitrarily exclude from consideration any interests at all-as those who draw the line with reference to the possession of reason or language do. The capacity for suffering and enjoyment is a prerequisite for having interests at all, a condition that must be satisfied before we can speak of interests in a meaningful way.” (Animal Liberation Page 7)

I find Cabrera’s stance on nonhuman animals particularly weird and disappointing partly since he quotes philosophers such as Schopenhauer and Heidegger, who at least on this issue are not particularly relevant nowadays, despite that he knows Perter Singer. And I am not assuming that because Singer is one of the most famous moral philosophers of this current age, but since he quotes him in the book Introduction to a Negative Approach to Argumentation and in this questionnaire. Unfortunately, the quotes are about abortions and about intervention in nature, not about the moral status of animals, and that is quite a cheap cherry picking move by Cabrera, as although Peter Singer discussed many issues in practical ethics along the years, surly by far more than any other issue the moral status of animals is the one which is most identified with him, and surly Cabrera is familiar with his ideas on the matter, so the least he could have done is explain why he thinks they are wrong. I highly doubt that he could.

An intuitive counter response to Cabrera might be that actually nonhuman animals are the ones with which it is very easy for each antinatalist to assist by going vegan and by that reduce the number of created creatures, and by supporting spay and neuter of cats and dogs, and by donating to animal organizations whose activities practically reduce the number of created creatures for example. It is true that it is a very effective and easy way to practically promote antinatalism, but the main resistance to Cabrera’s stance should be general and ethical not personal and practical. His claims are simply speciesist and it needs to be said.
Countering his claim requires an embarrassing repetition of ideas, which I was sure are long ago behind us, such as the ones Peter Singer wrote more than 45 years ago.

It seems that Cabrera is mixing moral agency with moral patiency. Nonhuman animals may not be ‘open to’ the domain of moral agency meaning moral obligations don’t apply to them for the reasons that he mentions along his answer, but he doesn’t explain why nonhuman animals are not ‘open to’ the domain of moral patiency meaning moral agents do have moral obligations towards them.
Moral obligations are not necessarily about moral relationships, but about moral relations, meaning how we are supposed to relate to others. And that is supposed to be based solely upon the ability to experience, not upon the ability to be in moral relationships with others.

His stance is not only a groundless omission of every sentient creature who is not a human, but it is also supposed to be a groundless omission of every human who is mentally incapable of moral relationships such as infants, severely cognitively disabled people and etc., or in other words whom who are referred to as marginal cases of humanity. Once the criterion for moral status is the ability to be in moral relationships then the only way to nevertheless include marginal cases of humanity – people who can’t take moral responsibility – within the moral community is based on a morally irrelevant criterion which is their species. On the face of it, according to Cabrera, since children until a certain age and people with various mental issues are not open to the domain of morality they are not supposed to be the recipients of moral treatment. If Cabrera wants to include people who do not possess the relevant cognitive abilities that are required for moral relationships within the moral community, that can only be on the bases of speciesism. That would turn the criterion for moral status from ability to participate and understand moral issues into whom who were born a human. And that’s speciesism.
Most people don’t accept (even if unconsciously) the ability to be in moral relationships as a morally justified criterion for moral status. When it comes to humans, most people think that cognitive abilities are morally irrelevant and sentience alone is sufficient to grant all of them with full moral consideration. The only reason they exclude sentient nonhuman animals is speciesism.

Let’s examine the earlier quoted claim that Cabrera makes about Contractualism:

“We can only have contracts with other humans, because a contract requires moral (or immoral) interaction. But this must not lead to mistreatment. It is incorrect and disgusting to make animals suffer or kill for fun, but it is not “immoral”, because morality requires reciprocity; it cause us discomfort to see animals suffer, but not all discomfort is a moral discomfort. If we cannot have contracts with nonhuman animals, and we don’t want to mistreat them either, we must find some kind of treatment with them, which consists of not harming them and benefiting them if possible.”

Let’s say for the sake of the argument that to claim that something is disgusting doesn’t necessarily mean that it is immoral (a claim which is not very clear, certainly not when it comes to relationships with others, since when something is disgusting clearly there is something wrong with it), but it surly can’t be argued that something is incorrect yet not immoral.
It seems that Cabrera is a bit confused when it comes to nonhuman animals. He doesn’t want to support cruelty or to be indifferent towards it, but he refuses to include them in the moral community, and so he goes back and forth with the issue. According to the first paragraph nonhuman animals are excluded. According to the second paragraph nonhuman animals are included but asymmetrically. According to the first line in the third paragraph nonhuman animals are excluded, however on the next sentence they are included, and on the sentence after that they are included, but only to be excluded again right after that. Then he turns to some sort of an emotive argument claiming that animals deserve some kind of moral treatment because ‘it cause us discomfort to see animals suffer”, and not that animals’ suffering is morally wrong because it causes animals discomfort. In the end of this paragraph he leaves nonhuman animals excluded because they can’t have contracts with humans, and speciesistly suggests that we must find some kind of treatment with them if we don’t want to mistreat them, that is not because humans most certainly shouldn’t mistreat sentient nonhuman animals, but because humans don’t want to.

His groundless insistence on the need to have a contract with nonhuman animals in order for them to have a moral status becomes particularly ridiculous when he explains why he is against abortions, despite that obviously, if having a contract with other humans is the necessary criterion for moral status then fetuses most definitely shouldn’t be included in the moral community.

The issue of abortion is brought up in question 21 so I’ll jump to it now and later come back to his answers to questions 19 and 20.

Question 21:

The following are the four versions of questions regarding abortion that were presented in the Questionaire:

“Your ideas surrounding abortion seem to be counter-intuitive to many in the antinatalist community. Is a fetus a “moral person” that deserves to be free of manipulation? Does this moral personhood begin even before consciousness is possible?”

“I’d like to understand why he feels that abortion is a violation of the foetus’s autonomy if the foetus is not conscious and aware of its existence, and why the principle of not violating the ‘autonomy’ of something unaware of its own existence is more important than the suffering that would be prevented by aborting it.
This is something I find utterly baffling about Cabrera’s antinatalism, and I will be interested to hear if he can explain it – People have said he’s anti-abortion.”

“does he think it’s important to preserve the life of something that has not even developed a capacity to desire to exist?”

“Does he think preserving the life of a nonhuman animal which is more sentient than a human fetus – a fish, for example – is more important or less important than preserving the life of a human fetus? – why would preserving the life of a fetus be thought to be more important than 1, preventing the suffering that would be experienced as a result of the complete creation of a sentience, and 2, the desires of the unwillingly pregnant?”

“What are his views about anti-abortion laws? Does he think the unwillingly pregnant should be forced to stay pregnant by law?”

Cabrera:

“Whoever formulates the issue of abortion imposes his own approach in the very formulation. That the human must be defined by the appearance of consciousness is not a fact: it is a presupposition that we have the right not to assume. My anti-abortion argument from negative ethics is extensively exposed in my books. In this argument, the fact that the embryo or the fetus are not “people”, that they have no “conscience” or “desire to exist” are totally irrelevant. I adopt an ontological-existential notion of humanity, inspired by phenomenological-hermeneutical (in the next and last question, I speak of the difficulties that antinatalists read only analytical literature, dispensing with the “continental”). This specific ontological mode of the human is characterized by the fact that he/she was asymmetrically thrown into the world contingently and towards death.  This happens long before the intellectual properties of awareness, self-awareness, rationality or language arise.”

If to continue the last line of thought from the previous question, the fact that the created person was asymmetrically thrown into the world contingently and towards death, can be said about nonhuman animals just as much yet, oddly, he deprives existing conscious and sentient nonhuman animals of moral status but grants fetuses with one.

And it gets even odder as it is not even the fetus itself who is granted with moral status despite not being conscious and sentient while existing conscious and sentient nonhuman animals are not, but it is the ontological-existential notion of humanity which is granted with moral status despite it not even being a morally relevant entity. The ontological-existential notion of humanity can’t feel, it doesn’t experience anything, it can’t be deprived of anything, yet according to Cabrera not only that this notion is a moral entity (and existing conscious and sentient nonhuman animals are not), it is in the center of his anti-abortion argument, and it justifies the creation of a person in case of conception, since the ontological-existential notion of humanity already exists, and terminating it by abortion is to manipulate it. Obviously, according to Cabrera not having an abortion is to manipulate the created person, therefore, given that he is anti-abortion, we must conclude that to manipulate the ontological-existential notion of humanity is morally worse than to manipulate an actual person.

Any sentience level is sufficient for someone to be morally considered, so there is no need to go as far as to the most intelligent social mammals, but I will go that far just to show how ridiculous this argument is, to compare an adult female elephant living in a complex fission-fusion society, being highly curious, aware of death, have a tremendous memory, great ability to solve problems, and etc., not even to an insentient heap of cells, but to the abstract notion of humanity, is to redefine speciesism. How disrespectful towards nonhuman animals’ actual experiences can one be to seriously consider merely the abstract ontological-existential notion of humanity as a moral entity, but not any nonhuman animal?

This claim remains very odd even if we’ll accept for the sake of the argument that notions can be treated as moral entities, because Cabrera himself argues that the ontological-existential notion of humanity is horrible and immoral, since, among other things, each person is “asymmetrically thrown into the world contingently and towards death”. And here are three more examples taken from his book Discomfort and Moral Impediment:

“Procreation is a structurally unilateral act in which one of the parties involved is brought to life by force through the action of others who decide that birth as a function of their own interests and benefits, or as a consequence of negligence”. (p. 129)

“Upon being born, we are thrust into a temporal process of gradual consumption and exhaustion characterized by pain (already expressed by a newborn baby’s crying when faced with the aggressions of light, sounds and the unknown), by discouragement (not knowing what to do with oneself, with one’s own body, with one’s own desires, something that babies will begin to suffer shortly after their birth); and lastly, by what I will call moral impediment, meaning being subjected to the pressing and exclusive concern with oneself and the necessity of using others for one’s own benefit (and being used by them).” (p. 25)

“As we are thrust into a world affected by structural discomfort, submitted to pain and discouragement and forced to act in an entangled web of actions within small spaces and under pressing time, we cannot avoid harming other humans in concrete situations of the intra-world, even those who we intend to help or benefit. At certain points in time, we are all provokers of harm. In an existential sense, we contribute to the discomfort of others.” (p. 66)

Hence, it would make more sense that if anything, his perceptions would intensify the argument for abortion, not establish claims against it.

But Cabrera insists:

“What is relevant to our question here is that since the moment of conception in a human body, we already have an existing one thrown over there, contingent, meaningless and towards death, even if this being has no first person awareness of that condition, nor any defined identity. In my own terms, it is a terminal human thing that has already begun to end, not potentially, but now.”

But who is the victim of this condition before that person has first person awareness? Who is harmed by the fact that a heap of cells have already begun to form? All the more so what’s wrong with ending it before that heap of cells has first person awareness, especially considering that it is necessarily a case of “an existing one thrown over there, contingent, meaningless and towards death”?
Since the issue is of abortion, it means that the parents do not wish to create a person, at least not in that current pregnancy, so they are not the victims of the abortion as they want it. If anything they would be the victims of not having an abortion, because they would be forced to create a person against their will. Does the ontological-existential notion of humanity overpower their interests as well? And more importantly, given that creating a person is not only creating a subject of harm, but a small unit of exploitation and pollution, the question mustn’t only be is it justified that people would be imposed to create a person against their will, since “since the moment of conception in a human body, we already have an existing one thrown over there, contingent, meaningless and towards death”, but also is it justified that numerous existing conscious and sentient nonhuman animals would be harmed by another unit of suffering, exploitation and pollution since “since the moment of conception in a human body, we already have an existing unit of suffering, exploitation and pollution thrown over there, contingent, meaningless and towards death”? Since it is never justified, procreation is never justified, and abortion always is.

How can a notion be morally more important than the real interests of real people – the parents who decided that they don’t want to create that person, and the interests of the main victims of most procreations – all the nonhuman animals that would be hurt if abortion doesn’t  take place?

Cabrera tries to explain:

“Benatar claims that “coming into existence” cannot be determined only biologically. I totally agree with him. In my approach, this terminal being and “towards death” aroused in the conception is not experienced, of course, in the first person, but is seen in the second and third person by the others involved. The humanity of a human is not just something given biologically, but also something socially constructed. The others will be able to confer or refuse human status to what is, for now, a heap of cells. They are capable to give the embryo and the fetus their humanity or refuse it. The procreated may or may not be part of the moral community depending on the decision of these third parties. Humanity does not need to be experienced in the first person to be recognized.

In these terms, what is immoral about abortion? When you have an abortion you eliminate in a manipulative and unilateral way someone else’s terminality, even if it is not yet a determined person. Even though – in the pessimistic perspective that I endorse – life is something terrible, we have no right to decide for another being that is already as terminal, absurd and thrown in the world toward death as we are. In this line of argument, abortion is immoral because it is a manipulative act, done for our convenience and offensive to an autonomy that is in the present recognizable in the third person.”

Resisting abortions is not considering the interests of third parties, but crushing the interests of first parties as created people never asked to be born, never gave consent to be harmed while existing, and are imposed with a constant risk of a miserable life, and it is crushing the interests of second parties, meaning the ones who would be mostly and most directly affected by the decision not to have an abortion, and these are the person’s parents, and much more than them – everyone who would be harmed by that person all along its existence.

Would he argue that by saving someone else’s life we eliminate in a manipulative and unilateral way someone else’s terminality? If we prevent someone’s murder is it also considered by his terms to eliminate in a manipulative and unilateral way someone else’s terminality?
And why is the notion of terminality morally more important than actual harm to actual sentient creatures? Again we encounter his odd priorities, as the notion of manipulation is prioritized over suffering. And in this case it is not even the manipulation of the created person, or of the created person’s parents, or of the created person’s victims, but the manipulation of an autonomy that is in the present recognizable in the third person. So the abstract notion of autonomy, which is merely present in some of the least affected people, defeats everything else. Does this line of thought work with other issues as well? Does the abstract notion of racism, which is merely present in some of the least affected people, defeat everything else as well?
Was the abolition of slavery immoral because it was a manipulative act, done for salves’ convenience and was offensive to the autonomy of the notion of white supremacy that was recognizable in the third person? What right do we have to reject the notion of white supremacy? Is it because white supremacy is most definitely morally wrong? Well, isn’t procreation most definitely morally wrong even according to Cabrera himself?

But Cabrera is sure that everyone who wonders how he can be anti-abortion is missing something:

“People who read my writings without due attention, wonder how can one be antinatalist and anti-abortion at the same time. After all, if life is so bad, do we have a duty to prevent more humans from being thrown into this terrible world? But this is a very simple-minded argument. If we think more carefully we can see that the situation of procreation and the situation of abortion have different logical and ethical structures.
In abstention we think from nothing, while in abortion we think from something. In the case of abstention there is nothing about which we have moral dilemmas before which we must stand. We can say that while procreation is preventable medicine, abortion is therapeutic medicine; and nothing can make abortion preventive.

Therefore, in the case of abstention, it is the consideration of the terrors of existence that prevails over autonomy, because there is no autonomy to respect (unless conjectured, with all the problems that this entails). In the case of abortion, the respect for autonomy prevails, an autonomy that already exists in the third person as a social and interactive fact.”

In abstention we don’t think from nothing, but also from something, that is from a place of resistance to create a person in the better case, or from a specific lack of want to create a person in the less good case. The case of abstention is thinking from something and not from nothing, it is at least thinking from something undesirable if not unacceptable. Once someone is in the position of abstention it means that that someone wishes to abstain from creating someone, and that is thinking from something.
In both cases there is a notion of humanity, in the case of abstention people are trying to prevent it, and in the case of abortion they are also trying to prevent it. The only difference is biological, and ironically Cabrera is the one who claims that abortion is not a biological issue.

Besides, isn’t abstention supposed to be, according to Cabrera, a manipulative act done for our convenience, and offensive to an autonomy that is in the present recognizable in the third person as well? I think it is, since clearly people choose abstention exactly because they have a notion of humanity which they wish to avoid, in general, or specifically in that given sexual act. So, is any use of contraception a manipulative act, done for our convenience and offensive to an autonomy that is in the present recognizable in the third person? Cabrera claims that the humanity of a human is not just something given biologically, but also something socially constructed, if that is the case we don’t need a heap of cells for abortion to be morally wrong, the very idea of creating a human is sufficient, and therefore isn’t any use of contraception morally wrong because it is a manipulation of the notion of humanity? Isn’t every case of people choosing not to breed a manipulation of humanity? As what do people who choose not to breed actually say, that they can create a human and choose not to, how isn’t that a manipulation of the notion of humanity?

There is, no incongruity at all in being antinatalist and anti-abortion; on the contrary: if the accent is put on manipulation (as is the case with negative ethics), it is almost mandatory to be both; because the same type of manipulation appears, only in opposite directions: when the child is desired, it is manipulated in procreation, and when it is unwanted it is manipulated in abortion; in both cases the terminal being is treated as a thing.

Only that in one case there is a harmed person, harmed parents and numerous harmed creatures who the created person would harm along its life, and in the other case the “victim” is the notion of humanity. We have a very serious and certain harm on one side, and none at all on the other.
By the way, most of acute opponents of abortion don’t fight it in the name of humanity but in the name of god. It is not the manipulation of humanity which they are concerned about, but the manipulation of god. Now since there isn’t one, there are no real victims of abortions. On the other hand, there are plenty of victims to each and every case that abortion wasn’t performed.

Cabrera argues that the created person should have the opportunity to decide later what to do about being thrown into the terrors of the world:

“It is true that by not aborting we throw this being into the terrors of the world, but at least, late on, this terminal being will be in a better position to decide what to do with its terminality; this will not be entirely decided by the others.”

No, it is anyway entirely decided by others. Only that in the case of abortion others decide that a person won’t be created and therefore won’t be harmed and harm others, and in the case that abortion wasn’t performed, it is others who decide that a person would be created and therefore be harmed and harm others.
Because of life’s addictive element, a created person doesn’t really decide what to do with its terminality, but is prone to continue living and therefore to suffer, vainly hoping that someday things would get better. Something that is very unlikely to happen.
Besides, there are no real better “positions” to decide what to do with one’s terminality. It is impossible to undo existence. Existence can’t be canceled. One cannot retroactively erase its own existence, only to end it, but there is no good exit plan. Suicide is a terrible exit plan because even people who really suffer in life are usually afraid of death, of pain, of permanently disabling themselves if they don’t succeed, of committing a sin, of their family, of the unknown, of breaking the law, of being socially shamed, of being blamed for selfishness, of the isolation ward in a psychiatric hospital and etc. So the suicide option is not very tempting in the better case, and nonviable in the worst.
It is false from every perspective to present suicide as a legitimate option available to anyone at any time. Biologically, suicide is the last option. And the fact that people are biologically built to survive, doesn’t soothe individuals whose lives are not worth living in their eyes, but exactly the opposite. They are prisoners of their own biological mechanisms. They are life’s captives, not free spirits who can choose to end their lives whenever and however they wish. People are trapped in horrible lives without a truly viable option to end it.
People have no serious exit option that can justify their forced entry. Not that if there was any, procreation was morally justifiable (as it still necessitates the suffering until the decision to end life is made), but at least this part of the argument was decent and coherent. But there isn’t an exit option so it is not. People must overcome too many obstacles with each being too difficult, for suicide to really be an option.
No one should put anyone in such a horrible position where they don’t want to live but are trapped in life.
Tens of millions of people are forced to live day after day after day, feeling that they don’t want to live, but are afraid of carrying out suicide, or that they are even in a deeper trap, can’t stand living but can’t stand the thought of hurting others by killing themselves. This is the cruel trap many people are forced to endure because they were created. The option of suicide is not a legitimate solution for the problem of procreation, but in fact another of its many evils.

But when it comes to actual cases he is less determined and more ambiguous:

“Anyway, there is no logical sequence form (I) abortion is immoral to (II) one should never abort. For we can be totally convinced of the immorality of abortion, but understand that, in many dramatic cases, women had to abort. Negative ethics is limited to saying that, as understandable as this act may be, these people will be doing something ethically wrong. Whoever aborts is certainly not a criminal (as the anti-abortionists sometimes rhetorically proclaim), but neither can we say that they are totally morally correct people.

I suppose that in order to solve the dramatic cases, it may be better to resort to some utilitarian or pragmatic procedure, even if the immorality of abortion is theoretically recognized (in my line of argument or other).”

What does it mean whoever aborts is certainly not a criminal but neither can we say that they are totally morally correct people? And what are according to him dramatic cases? Does he mean cases of rape? Extreme poverty? Foreseen severe impairments? All of the above? And isn’t the notion of humanity manipulated in these cases as well? Could it be that terms such as ‘suffering’ and ‘justified’ somehow have found their way into the discussion when he needed to approve some cases of abortion?
It’s clear to him that he cannot oppose abortions on every case so he permits the ones he calls dramatic cases, but without detailing why and which cases are dramatic.
It seems that when he needs to encounter a real issue from real life, he ditches his ideas of negative ethics and suggests that “it may be better to resort to some utilitarian or pragmatic procedure”. But why? Is it because he knows that he cannot look in the eyes of a raped woman and tell her that she must raise the child of her rapist because otherwise it would be to manipulate the notion of the child’s humanity? And isn’t an ethical theory supposed to address all cases and if not, to at least coherently explain why some cases are exceptional?

Cabrera realizes that his ideas are not really perfectly viable and so he pulls his perspectivistic approach:

“This line of argument is perfectly viable and it will be seen as “counter-intuitive” only if the other parts impose their own assumptions; assuming mine, my posture is perfectly intuitive and theoretically sustainable. As I am also a logical pessimist, I do not believe in absolute conclusions. What I presented here was just a line of sustainable argument. Abortion can be morally legitimate in one line of argument and morally illegitimate in another. We don’t need to destroy each other because of that.”

But for whom who is forced to be created, for whom who is forced to create, and for whom who are forced to be harmed by the created, procreation is indeed extremely destructive.

Question 19:

The following are the four versions of questions regarding EFILism that were presented in the Questionaire:

“Are you familiar with the subject of EFILism, and if so do you think about it? EFILists essentially believe that sentient life should be placed in plaintive care, in hospice so to speak, and that there should be direct intervention in ending wild life suffering, even if the only option is to find a way of euthanizing them. What are your thought on that? I believe that Antinatalsim/EFILism are essentially the final civil rights movement – that there is nowhere for the subject of suffering mitigation to go from there, and that not being imposed upon to exist can and should be seen as a sentient creatures most supreme civil rights. What do you think of this idea?”

“Do you believe that the concept of Antinatalism should be extended to all sentient creatures? Do you believe that a goal of Antinatalism should be the extinction of both humans and animals? I feel it would be the greatest tragedy we could allow, for humans to go extinct before the animals, nature is where most of the suffering is on planet earth – thoughts?”

“Have you thought about extending your ideas about antinatalism to the whole of animal kingdom? Jeremy Bentham asked “the question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? But, can they suffer?” today we know the answer. Animals do suffer. What can we do about that? What are Cabrera’s thoughts on wild-animal suffering and that there would be much more of it if only humans went extinct?”

“Would you extend antinatalism to nonhuman animals as well? There is an enormous amount of suffering in the nonhuman world, do we have an ethical duty to end that suffering? What can we do knowing that people will still be procreating? What can we be doing knowing that the antinatalist project will never come to be? Does that also extent to animal rights?”

Cabrera:

“As we saw in the previous question, in negative ethics we cannot have ethical relations with animals, as they have no moral impediment. Therefore, if negative ethics were in agreement with the extinction of nonhuman animals, it could not be for ethical reasons, strictly speaking. That is why I would not accept this idea of “extending” the ethics of humans to nonhumans; because as they have ontologically different ways of being, there is nothing to “extend”; the attitude towards nonhuman animals must be invented post-morality in a particular way.

Leaving aside the contract, which is impossible, we are left with treatment and mistreatment. We have to see if the extinction of nonhuman animals could be included in treatment, or if the extinction would generate some kind of mistreatment. If the first were possible, negative ethics could approve the procedure. But if in order to extinguish them we had to mistreat them some way, negative ethics cannot accept to suppress nonhuman animals, even if the extinction is intended to be “for their own good”.”

The implication of this stance is that since humans cannot have ethical relations with animals, but they can mistreat them (and I’ll ignore for the sake of the argument the contradiction between these two statements), then even if all that it would take to end all the suffering that every nonhuman animal that would ever exist, is the pain of one pinprick for each currently existing nonhuman animal (which quantitively speaking is just a fraction of the number of nonhuman animals that would ever exit), Cabrera would oppose it because that would be humans mistreating nonhuman animals. That means that the actual experiences of the infinite number of sentient creatures that would exist if humans don’t inflict the pain of one pinprick for each currently existing nonhuman animal, are worth so little in his view, that the abstract virtuousness of humans undoubtedly overpowers it. And that is undoubtedly one of the cruelest ideas I can think of. Obviously, unfortunately that scenario is absolutely delusional but it is ethical. There is nothing better or a more important goal than ending all the suffering of all the creatures in the world. Apparently not according to Cabrera. He rather that an infinite number of nonhuman animals would endure life of suffering than the option that much less humans would allegedly mistreat much less nonhuman animals.
But ethics should first and foremost be concerned with actual suffering of anyone who is capable of experiencing it, not with the supposed incorruptibility of one species, especially since it is irrelevant to the sufferers. Ethics should focus on pain and distress wherever they happen and to whomever. It should be concerned with the actual cruel fates of the victims, not with the fictional purity of the moral agents.

It seems however, that Cabrera is more bothered with what humans would do than with what would happen to infinitely more nonhuman animals.
And it shouldn’t come as a surprise since as we have seen in his explanations of his basic stands regarding antinatalism, he is focused on the ontological position of humans, not on the actual experiences of the rest of the sentient creatures in the world. The fact that this world is actually a planetary scale restaurant, in which everyone is suffering, is not his motive. His drive is not the suffering but the ‘ontological-existential notion’, and not of everyone but of one species only.

Here is an example from the very same answer:

“Ultimately, I consider humanity as the primordial biological catastrophe of nature and think that life is not so calamitous if it does not have reflexive self-awareness.”

“…hence the animals’ unconcern and tranquility, so worthy of envy. Animal suffering is much more integrated with nature; it is not enough to say, like Bentham: ‘they also suffer’.”

“I really wouldn’t have a problem with a planet without humans and with nonhuman animals living in their natural surroundings. What did not work is the human life; the other animals are fine as they are and would be much better off without the suffering introduced by humans.
God should have stopped creation before the sixth day. It would be good to leave nonhuaman animals in their lives of harsh survival and spontaneous violence. It is true that humans care for animals and protect them from certain hostile environments. But it is also true that they hunt, eat and mistreat them. I think the best thing we can do for animals is to disappear and leave them alone.”

The issue of self-awareness among nonhuman animals is factually and morally controversial. Only a speciesist would put all the nonhuman animals under the same category despite that clearly the similarity between other social mammals (let alone other primates) and humans, is far greater than the similarity between social mammals and sponges or earthworms, and yet, earthworms and orangutans are on the same group, and humans are on a whole different superior level. That is factually ridiculous. And it is factually noncontroversial that at least some social mammals are self-aware. But I don’t want to discuss it even if it serves the cause, because it is morally irrelevant and therefore wrong to focus on that. We can say that self-awareness can actually in many cases sooth and not enhance negative experiences, for example when one is aware that one’s injuries or maladies are not dangerous and easily treatable. That is as opposed to creatures who suffer from similar conditions but are unaware of their condition and therefore suffer more. But again, that is irrelevant in terms of moral status. Being self-aware to the fact that I am suffering right now is not necessary to establish my moral status. The fact that I am suffering is sufficient. I don’t need the ability to self-reflect on my negative experience for it to be negative. The ability to have a negative experience is sufficient.
Experiencing extreme fear every single time someone goes out of the cave to drink is horrible for anyone who experiences it, without being self-aware that extremely fearing every single time someone goes out of the cave to drink is horrible. This experience is horrible without reflecting on its horribleness. Extreme fear needs not reflexive self-awareness to be horrible. It is horrible as it is. Fear is fear, and pain is pain. One doesn’t need to have reflexive self-awareness to feel fear and pain. Not reflexive self-awareness is the crucial component in moral status but sentience. What really matters in morality is not self-awareness but the experience of pain and suffering.

So it is most definitely enough to say, like Bentham that they also suffer.
And the claim that “animal suffering is much more integrated with nature” is a super-anthropocentric, speciesist, nature worshiping, and extremely ignorant claim.

To claim that other animals “would be much better off without the suffering introduced by humans” is probably one of the greatest understatements ever made. And the claim that “other animals are fine as they are” is probably one of the greatest misstatements ever made.
As argued elsewhere, procreation is a very serious crime because the ample evidences that bad experiences are more important than good ones, not only serve as a proof that good experiences are at least not as good as bad experiences are bad (if not proving that bad experiences almost always outweigh the good ones), but how horrible life actually and inherently is. Basically, pain and other negative experiences increase the fitness of individuals by enhancing their respondence ability to threats to their survival and reproduction. It has a crucial adaptive function. Existing sentient creatures are tortured by evolutionary mechanisms which their only point is that additional sentient creatures would exist, regardless of any of those creatures’ personal wellbeing. It is a pointless, frustrating and painful trap.

Probably the strongest evidence for that, and one of the strongest arguments for including animals living in nature in antinatalism, is that by far the vast majority of individuals in nature never reach adulthood, with most living short lives of nothing but fear and pain.

Most people, and disappointedly it seems that Cabrera is among them, think of mammals when they contemplate about nature. But even among mammals – the class with the highest survival rates – the vast majority of individuals never reach adulthood. And by far most of the individuals in nature are not mammals. The reproductive strategy of by far most of the species in nature is r-selection, meaning that most animals reproduce between hundreds to hundreds of thousands of children (some even millions), with usually only few who reach adulthood, and only two who survive long enough to reproduce (that is the case in any stable population since otherwise we would have seen a massive population increase).

Obviously what matters morally is suffering, not adulthood rates. But behind the astonishing survival figures in nature, which reach less than one percent among many species (probably most), are innumerable suffering individuals who experienced nothing but suffering in their short brutal lives. It goes to show how dispensable sentient individuals lives are in nature. The fact that most of the creatures who are created in this world are born only to suffer is not only absolutely natural, but is nature in its essence. And so, probably most relevantly to antinatalism, is that in the case of animals in nature there should be absolutely no doubt that for the absolutely vast majority of creatures, coming into existence is a very serious harm.

As I argued earlier, I don’t think that from all the philosophers and other thinkers, Schopenhauer is the one to be based on when it comes the status of nonhuman animals, but if he chose to rely on him in this context, he should be reminded of another Schopenhauer’s quote:

“A quick test of the assertion that enjoyment outweighs pain in this world, or that they are at any rate balanced, would be to compare the feelings of an animal engaged in eating another with those of the animal being eaten.”

And this claim is an even much stronger support of EFILism when considering that no animal is engaged merely in eating another, but with very many anothers, and that no animal being eaten is merely suffering from being eaten alive but from many other factors such as hunger, thirst, cold, heat, diseases, parasites, fear, fatigue, worn out and etc.

Despite all the things he said so far all along the questionnaire, he also argues that:

“The extinction procedure, even inspired by this beautiful purpose, can generate suffering in the animals that we are trying to benefit, within a macro project, can make them suffer. Maybe it would be necessary to create concentration camps for nonhuman animals; it would not be a peaceful procedure.”

But why does he call it a beautiful purpose if he claimed that “the other animals are fine as they are” and that “the best thing we can do for animals is to disappear and leave them alone”?
And why does he call it a beautiful purpose if there are no moral relationships with nonhuman animals? Shouldn’t he view it as neutral? If it is not neutral but good to end nonhuman animals suffering how is it not a moral requirement? How is it not even a moral issue given that he previously argued that there are no moral relationships between humans and nonhumans? He can counter-argue that we don’t have an obligation to save all the animals but it still is a beautiful purpose. But the reason it is a beautiful purpose is because it is the moral thing to do, or at least it is morally good to do so. And if a purpose is beautiful (moral) then we need to try and implement it, not state that it is beautiful. Beautiful purposes need to be practically actuated.

Unfortunately I agree that this beautiful purpose can’t be implemented by a peaceful procedure, but much more unfortunate is that I don’t think it can be implemented at all. I elaborate about this in the text about Efilism, but anyway this point is irrelevant to this discussion since my reservations about this purpose are only practical and by no means ethical. In my view moral duty stems from vulnerability not from relationships. We are morally obligated to help any vulnerable subject if we can, regardless of the species of the vulnerable subject or our relationship with the vulnerable subjects. Sentience is a sufficient criterion for moral status and a sufficient justification to try and prevent harms inflicted on any vulnerable subject. So obviously we must try to prevent any harm from any vulnerable subject, no matter who s/he is and where s/he is.
And obviously we most certainly mustn’t inflict harm on other vulnerable subjects, and since everyone always do, even the ones who are not eating animals or animal based products, everyone mustn’t procreate. No matter who someone is, where and how that someone lives, eventually everything is somehow at someone else’s expense. Existence is harmful and existing is harming. Negative ethics more than any other moral theory should be EFIList. It isn’t, only because it is speciesist. A non speciesist antinatalist approach must be EFIList. Or in other words, EFILism is antinatalism without speciesism.

Place suffering in the center of negative ethics and expend it beyond humans to every sentient creature on earth and you actually have a form of EFILism. There is more than one road to EFILism but this is certainly mine. That’s why when I first read A Critique of Affirmative Morality I thought that I finally found my “bible”. I still think it is a great book which is most definitely worth reading by any antinatalist let alone EFIList. However reading other texts by Cabrera, especially Introduction to a Negative Approach to Argumentation, and his answers to this questionnaire, made me realize that the problem I had with negative ethics go deeper than its feeble conclusions. There is no way around it, Cabreara’s Negative Ethics is speciesist.

I am talking with people about moral issues, especially of harming nonhuman animals for a long time now so I am used to their infinite moral flexibility when it comes to ideas they don’t want to embrace, but I didn’t expect that from the philosopher who wrote the book A Critique of Affirmative Morality. At that point I thought that the only reasonable explanation for his unequivocal senseless immoral excuses is that he doesn’t want to embrace veganism. And indeed came his awful answer to the question about veganism.

Question 20:

Many (but not all) antinatalists are vegans due to the incorporation of animals into their moral community. Are you a vegan? Irrespective of the answer: why? Why he isn’t vegan? If forcing nonhumans into the world for human consumption or to any other benefit compatible with antinatalism? And with that is there an ethical duty for antinatalists to be vegan and not pay for others to be brought into the world for their benefit?

Cabrera:

“As there is no possibility for me to incorporate animals into the moral community THAT cannot be the reason for being vegan or vegetarian. I have said before that this provide no reason to mistreat animals. The problem is that it seems evident that we mistreat them when we kill them for food. Therefore, it seems that we should radically refuse to feed on them.

I am not particularly vegan or vegetarian, although I completely eliminated beef, pork and fish from my diet many years ago; but I eat chicken often. This would seem to be a clear contradiction between my thinking and my life. Even though we cannot have ethical relationships with animals, and even though I am not concerned with extinguishing them, I agree with not mistreating them, and eating them clearly seems to be a kind of mistreatment.

The first argument to come out of this blatant contradiction is that I may need to eat some meat to preserve my health. The thesis that one can live in good health without eating animal proteins is controversial. I have consulted all kinds of medicines, orthodox and heterodox, and the opinions are the most varied, although each part affirms with total certainty to be right. On the other hand, one cannot speak generally of “human health”, but of individual bodies; what is not necessary for certain organisms may be necessary for others.

In my particular case, I feel weak and sleepy if I don’t eat some chicken meat for several days. Accepting that completely suppressing the consumption of some meat was clearly bad for my health, should I take the requirement not to mistreat animals to the point of damaging my health?

In negative ethics, we have no moral obligation to preserve our life or our health just to continue living; we can and must risk our lives because of some ethical requirement. But since we have no strictly ethical obligations to nonhuman animals, it would seem that this requirement to harm me in order to preserve them cannot be ethically justified. Nevertheless, we decided not to mistreat non human animals, but since this is not a moral principle, but only a beneficial practice, we can have the right to balance it with other morally relevant considerations, not to take it as a requirement without exception.

If I choose to preserve my health by continuing to eat birds, I could claim that I need my health not for satisfying frivolous gastronomic pleasures or for gluttony, but for to be able to continue doing things that I consider as morally important as the act of not eating animals; for example: fighting injustices, defending social movements, finishing a book against racism or doing activism in the antinatalist cause. I cannot assume a fanatic vegetarianism; I would have to consider, in specific cases, what are the social costs – not just personal, selfish or hedonistic – of stopping eating meat entirely. We cannot escape “spciesism” by falling into a kind of “animalism”; in some cases we may have to favor human animals and in others our option will be for nonhumans ones.”

Since I found his health excuse utterly insulting, I will not focus on nutritional matters here. I am anyway sure that it is totally needless for any of the readers of this text. The fact that everyone can maintain healthy life on a plant based diet is, as opposed to his claim, not controversial. Like the philosophers he chose to quote so to base his speciesist stands on the moral status of nonhuman animals, his nutritionist basis is also irrelevant and outdated.
Anyway, it is more interesting and relevant to focus here on veganism and antinatalism from his negative ethics perspective.

If antinatalism is an opposition to the imposition involved with the creation of a vulnerable person without consent and while risking that person having a miserable life, then when it comes to animals in the food industry, there is no doubt that it is an imposition that involves the creation of a vulnerable creatures without consent, and it is not risking them having a miserable life, but insuring that they would have miserable lives full of abuse and torture.
Antinatalists justly refuse to impose harm on a person without obtaining that person’s consent, but the ones who are not vegan unjustly agree to impose harm on numerous animals without obtaining their consent. They don’t obtain their consent to be genetically modified so they would provide the maximum meat possible. They don’t obtain their consent to be imprisoned for their entire lives. They don’t obtain their consent to live without their family for their entire lives. They don’t obtain their consent to suffer chronic pain and maladies. They don’t obtain their consent to never breathe clean air, walk on grass, bath in water, and eat their natural food. They don’t obtain their consent to be violently murdered so that people could consume their bodies.
Animals exploited in the food industry are the most unequivocal example of sentient creatures who are forced to live in extreme misery during every single moment of their lives. In their case, extreme misery is not a risk that anyone involved in their creation is taking, but a decision. In their case, creation is not a Russian Roulette but a certain living hell.
These animals must be the first to be included in antinatalism. It is beyond me how someone can be an antinatalist but actively contribute to the creation of the most miserable lives on earth.

Not suffering but manipulation is in the center of Cabrera’s antinatalism, but when it comes to animals exploited in the food industry both take place in the most extreme manner. In their case there is no need to argue where should antinatalism’s focus should be. Everything about their lives is extreme suffering and a product of total manipulation. There are no more accurate examples of the manipulation involved with creation than the creation of sentient creatures whose only function is to become someone else’s stake, coat, shoes, sweater, omelet producer, milkshake producer, bacon, or poulet. Every year more than 150 billion sentient animals are manipulatively created and manipulatively reared, explicitly, merely to be used as means to others’ ends. Is there a greater manipulation involved in creation than that?
And the manipulation goes further than the concept of creating billions of sentient creatures merely to be used as means to others’ ends, as every single part of their lives involves manipulation, even before they are born. Their genetics is manipulated so they would produce more meat, milk and eggs, their social structure is manipulated so to make the control over them more “efficient”, their confinement facilities are manipulated so to reduce costs to the minimum, the lighting in their confinement facilities is manipulated so they would think it is daylight even when it is not and so eat more and get fatter faster, their living spaces are manipulated so they would be unable to move and won’t “waste” energy on anything but growing as fast as possible, their food is manipulated in order to reach what is referred to by the industry as the optimal food efficiency, their water availability is manipulated so they would urinate less and so their bedding wouldn’t be replaced during their short miserable lives.

There is nothing more manipulative than the creation and the lives of animals in the food industry, so a philosopher such as Cabrera, who in the center of his ethics is manipulation, must be the last person who can justify participating in such a mass scale systematical manipulation.

And of all creatures, he chooses to consume the one that goes through the greatest manipulations of all.
I would like to elaborate about the life of chickens in the meat industry because they are the strongest most evident example for why nonhuman animals must be included in antinatalism, especially when manipulation is in its center, as chickens exemplify more than any other creature the greatest and cruelest combination between suffering and manipulation.

The miserable life of every chicken in the meat industry starts when they hatch. Instead of being born to a defending, loving, and guiding mother, the first experience of every chick, is seeing thousands of other babies helplessly chirping to their absent mothers in the incubator they are born in.
Usually at the age of 2-3 days, all the newborn chicks are aggressively thrown into boxes and are shipped to the sheds where they would spend their entire miserable lives.
Despite that naturally chickens are social animals who spend most of their time foraging, they are forced to live their entire lives in crowded, dirty, soaked with ammonia warehouses, with no chance for any normal social structure, or any normal chicken behavior such as perching, foraging and dust bathing, no natural food, no sunshine, and no fresh air, which are all very essential for each chicken.

As the chickens grow, each one suffers not only from the diminishing space, but also from a series of severe health issues. That is mainly because chickens are being manipulated to grow about three times faster than normal, through a suited diet, special lighting plans, but mostly genetic modifications which aim to enlarge the more profitable body parts at the expense of the least profitable body parts of each bird. That causes each chicken to suffer from painful skeletal and metabolic diseases. At some point most of the chickens in each shed suffer from chronic pain and lameness.
The accelerated growth also prevents the chickens’ hearts and lungs from keeping up with the rest of the body, and so many suffer from related illnesses, among them are cardiac arrhythmia and heart attack. That is particularly amazing considering that chickens are slaughtered at the age of 7 weeks.

As the sheds get more crowded and filthier, the chickens who are forced to sit in wet, dirty, soaked with ammonia bedding, develop painful blisters, lesions and ulcerations on their already aching bodies. They often also develop painful eye infections as a result of the high ammonia concentration.

Their miserable lives are ended only by a miserable death. But before the chickens are slaughtered they suffer additional harms in the form of aggressive catching and loading onto the trucks, a horrible ride to the slaughterhouse in an extremely crowded truck, under every weather condition, no matter how freezing it is outside or alternatively how hot and dry it is, the chickens have no cover. Since it is unprofitable neither to feed the poor birds in their last day nor to give them any water, the chickens are starving and are dehydrated, a horrible condition which further contributes to the already extreme pain and stress.

The chickens are then aggressively pulled out of the cages in the trucks and aggressively shoved upside down into shackles on a conveyor belt. They are supposed to be stunned by electrified water, but many aren’t and so their throats are slashed while fully conscious. Some are even thrown into the boiling scalding tank, which looses their feathers before plucking, while still fully conscious, that means that they will be conscious when the plucking knives tear their bodies.

None of what is the written in the following paragraph is a recommendation, as no one needs to blow up the face of another animal to feed itself, but as an antinatalist, all the more so one that so highly emphasizes the manipulative aspect of creation, Cabrera could have at least argued that the only animal based product that he consumes is the meat of particularly large mammals who were hunted in the least harmful way. The rationale behind this is that particularly large mammals would provide him with meat for a long time and so the minimum number of animals would have to be sacrificed for his groundless speciesist and cruel insistence on consuming animals. The least harmful way is self-explanatory, and the hunting part is also highly related with the least harmful way as anything is better than factory farming, but it also relates to antinatalism as seemingly, hunting as opposed to the meat industry doesn’t necessarily mean that another animal would be produced. Practically it is very probable that another animal would because of how nature works (ecological niches tend to be populated according to available resources so when animals are murdered by humans other animals usually shortly occupy the area), but it is not as bound and structured as it is in the food industry. But more than the claimed above, the manipulation part is less present in hunting than it is in industrial exploitation of animals. So Cabrera of all people should have been highly opposed to the industrial manipulation and creation of other animals. But he considers nonhuman animals so little that he didn’t even bother thinking about options which would at least be less embarrassing than the bewildering self-contradiction that he made.
His response is insulting as it seems that he didn’t even bother respecting his questioners and listeners by giving a plausible answer. But of course the real problem, and the reason I mention this, is to exemplify how little importance and significance the suffering of trillions of animals matter to an ethical philosopher, and how deeply troubling must that be to all of us.

In the book A Critique of Affirmative Morality, Cabrera wrote a short Survival Handbook where he argues that since it is not optional to simply live and thereby affirmatively experiencing the world, one must conduct life which is ontologically minimal, radically responsible, sober, and completely aware that it is only a secondary morality, he calls it Negative Minimalism.
I fail to see Negative Minimalism in consuming animal products. It is the cruelest, least thoughtful, most wasteful and extremely environmentally unfriendly way one can feed itself. Supporting factory farms is Negative Maximalism. And when it is coming from someone like him, it is beyond inconsistency, it is criminal. This is not to be taken as a case of Ad Hominem. Cabrera is not another non-vegan antinatalist, he is the philosopher behind Negative Ethics. The case in point is that ironically he himself exemplifies an even stronger version of his own theory of how impossible it is for one to be ethical. His argument is that ethics is impossible even theoretically because not harming and not manipulating others is impossible even theoretically, but he gives us a personal example of how even in cases which it is theoretically possible not to harm and manipulate at least some others, practically people would choose to do so anyway.
The fact that people can’t avoid harming and manipulating others even if they wanted to, is a sufficient reason to stop the effort of trying to convince them to stop procreating and start the effort of making them stop procreating. The fact that they don’t even want to, makes that case indisputable.

Questioning Julio Cabrera’s Questionnaire – Part 1 – Off-Center

In the following texts I will comment on some of Julio Cabrera’s replies to questions he was asked in The Exploring Antinatalism Podcast #19 – Julio Cabrera ‘Questionaire on Antinatalism’.

I find this episode very interesting and highly important with many issues worth addressing. Therefore I decided to divide my review into three parts:
Cabrera’s general approach to Antinatalism, His approach to animals (and also to EFILism, Veganism and Abortion), and the last part is dedicated to the question of .
Another very important issue which was brought up in question number 10, but mostly in question number 15, regards his perspectivist stands elaborated in his book “Introduction to a Negative Approach to Argumentation”. But since I have addressed this issue as part of a critical review of the book, and especially in the appendix of that review which was specifically dedicated to the issue of perspectivism, I’ll not address it here as well.

In this first part I’ll address questions regarding his general approach to Antinatalism.

I would like to use this opportunity of mentioning The Exploring Antinatalism Podcast to highly recommend everyone to listen to each and every episode of it. I think it is an ethical and an intellectual treasure, and that the people involved in it are doing an outstanding job. We highly differ on the practical level, meaning on what we think must be done regarding antinatalism, but we highly agree on the theoretical level, meaning that we all must be sentinetcentered EFILists.

Question 2:

“Can you explain to me your general position on the subject of antinatalism?”

Cabrera:

“I accept the central idea: better not to be born, better not procreate. But I have three reservations. First, antinatalism is, in my case, just a part of a negative ethics, which is based on a negative ontology. The problem of procreation is a special problem, not the central one; and it does not appear out of nowhere, but within a complex system of ideas. Secondly, my antinatalism is not centered on the issue of suffering, but on manipulation. Thirdly, antinatalists are ethical pessimists, but they remain logical optimists. All of these questions will be clarified throughout the questionnaire. But these ethical and logical reservations are not enough to undermine the central antinatalist idea.”

Since I’ve already broadly addressed negative ethics in the text dedicated to text dedicated to Cabrera’s book A Critique Of Affirmative Morality, I’ll only briefly argue here that antinatalism shouldn’t be just a part of a negative ethics but its main derived conclusion especially since Cabrera’s negative ethics is based on a negative ontology, meaning (based on his article from History of Antinatalism, Pages 168-169) life as imposed at birth constitutes a situation that causes a sensible and moral discomfort, which is not merely empirical but structural, based on the phenomenon of terminality of being, on the crude fact that all things are terminal, in the sense of things that begin to end at their very starting point, and not calmly but painfully, affected by all kinds of frictions and hardships. And in trying to escape from terminality, humans harm others; they become terminal to each other. The main impact of terminality in humans is the phenomenon of moral impediment – the impossibility of being ethical in the sense of not manipulating and not harming others.
In an article called Summary of The Ethical Question in Julio Cabrera’s Philosophy, Cabrera writes that:

“a negative life shall emerge, basically, on four ideas: (a) Full conscience about the structural disvalue of human life, assuming all the consequences of it; (b) Structural refuse to procreation (a negative philosopher with children is even more absurd than an affirmative one without them); (c) Structural refuse to heterocide (not killing anybody in spite of the frequent temptation to violence); (d) Permanent and relaxed disposition for suicide as a possibility.”

Now, since the only way to avoid the structural disvalue of human life, to avoid violence of all kinds, to all creatures, at all times, and to avoid the complexity and hardships of suicide as a possibility, is not to procreate, I think that antinatalism should nevertheless play the central role in negative ethics.
According to negative ethics life is structurally unethical. What then can be more central than the derived conclusion that procreation is morally unethical?

Regarding his claim that his antinatalism is not centered on the issue of suffering but on manipulation, in the article which I’ve just quoted from, he writes that procreation is in any case morally problematic because “it consists in providing to others the terminal structure of being and its consequent pain, tedium and moral disqualification”, so if indeed it is the manipulation which is in the center of his antinatalism then procreation is morally problematic because the created persons were manipulated into a terminal structure of being and its consequent pain, tedium and moral disqualification, and not because the created persons are in a terminal structure of being and its consequent pain, tedium and moral disqualification. In other words, it seems that according to Cabrera the act of manipulation by the parents is morally more important than the actual state of their children – the created persons. That is despite that the created persons might not be aware of or view their creation as a manipulation, while they all feel pain, tedium and are structurally morally disqualified (even if they may not be aware of or care much about the last defect). In my view, structural manipulation can never be morally more important than how the manipulated creatures actually feel. Or put it even more simply, the central problem with “providing to others the terminal structure of being and its consequent pain, tedium and moral disqualification”, is not that the providing is manipulative but that the pain, tedium and moral disqualification are harmful.
If it is the manipulation and not the suffering which makes procreation wrong, would procreation be wrong even if there was nothing wrong with pain, tedium and moral disqualification, as long as the created persons were manipulated into a terminal structure of them? And would procreation not be wrong, if the created persons weren’t manipulated but still in a terminal structure of being and its consequent pain, tedium and moral disqualification?

Even if only few people suffered during their lives and all people were manipulated, suffering should still be the center of antinatalism because experiences of actual people are more ethically important than abstract notions, no matter how unethical they abstractly are. If no one is hurt by an abstract notion then it is morally meaningless.
It is morally meaningless to manipulate water in itself, as water are not subjects, they don’t feel anything. They don’t experience their manipulation on any level. Manipulating water is morally meaningful only if it affects the experience of sentient creatures who live in or rely on it. The basic unit of ethics is experience, not abstract notions such as manipulation.

In his answer to a different question (Number 12), he said:

“In favor of antinatalism, I think that the manipulation argument is more striking than the suffering argument. The thesis “we should not have children because they will suffer”, face many counter-arguments; for example: there are also many good things in a human life, we are well equipped to endure suffering, suffering is relative to peoples and so on.
On the contrary, the thesis: “we should not have children because we manipulate them when we make them be born” it is something impossible to deny. There may be people who suffer little during their lives, but they were certainly manipulated at birth. Anyway, I use both arguments.
I show that life is full of suffering and that therefore, the “value of life” cannot justify manipulation.”

But suffering is also something impossible to deny, especially if like me, you think that many “good” things in a human’s life are not really intrinsically good but addictive falsehood smoke screen illusions, which trap sentient beings in an endless, pointless and vain seek for more of them. Pleasures are preceded by wants which are the absence of objects desired by subjects. People want because they are missing something. They seek pleasures to release the tension of the craving. Craving or wants, are at least bad experiences if not a sort of pain (I elaborate about this in the text about Benatar’s Asymmetry argument and its supplemental text about how bad is stronger than good).

And regardless of that the “good” things are actually not good, just as people can counter-argue that there are also many good things in a human’s life and so the suffering during it is worth it, they can just the same claim that the good things in life outweigh the manipulation. The manipulation argument is exposed to the same counter-argument that Cabrera claims that the suffering argument is exposed to. Anyone can say that the manipulation is not that bad and they are happy to be alive even if they were manipulated. Of course there is a lot to say about why many people state they are happy to be alive, and about how happy they really are, and for how long, and etc., but the point here is that it is not the argument of manipulation that would convince them otherwise but if anything, other arguments from other areas, most probably (but highly improbably) ones that involve theirs or their children’s suffering.

The fact that he admits that when he is challenged with his manipulation centered argument, he uses the suffering argument, all the more so claiming that life is full of suffering, goes to show that it’s the suffering and not the manipulation which tips the scales even according to his view.

He knows that not many would be convinced by the fact that people manipulate their children when they make them ‘be born’, but at least some may be convinced by the option that their children would suffer during their lives. He realizes that it is hard to be convinced by the argument that the “value of life” cannot justify manipulation in itself, so he must add the ‘full of suffering’ part, otherwise people might be rather indifferent to the fact that all people manipulate their children by making them ‘be born’ as long as their lives are good. Most people are not bothered with the fact their parents manipulated them when they made them ‘be born’. Most people are rather satisfied with this manipulation. It seems that most people are happy that they were created (or at least they state that they are) despite that it was a manipulation at their expanse. The ones who admit that they are not happy that they were created, usually feel this way because they are suffering during their lives, not because they were manipulated to be born.

But much more important than which argument can do a better job convincing people and dealing with counter-arguments, is which argument better describes the wrongness of procreation. The fact that there are not many people who feel that they are harmed by the fact that they were manipulated to be born, but there are many people who feel that they are harmed because of the suffering they endure during their lives, indicates that it is the suffering which should be in the center of antinatalism.
Contrary to the manipulation argument, one which centers suffering can base itself on the fact that there are people who can’t bare their own suffering in life and would rather never to have been, and that some of them kill themselves. On the other hand, it is highly unlikely that there are people who feel that their lives are not worth living and that some of them decide to kill themselves because their parents manipulated them to be born. People who kill themselves and people who seriously consider killing themselves, do it because they can’t bare their suffering in life, not because they can’t bare the fact that their life started as a manipulation. So it is the suffering argument which is more striking than the manipulation argument, and that is the argument which is less exposed to counter-arguments by people who most would probably severely underrate the chances of their children to suffer during their lives because of the optimism bias, but wouldn’t even understand how “giving” life to someone and loving them supposedly unconditionally is a manipulation. Obviously that is not to say that manipulation is not the case, of course it most definitely is, but few people can acknowledge this, while many can accept that suffering children is an option.

Question 6:

“Can you envisage a plausible mode of living that avoids (or diminishes to a trivial level) the “moral impediment” or is this an intrinsic feature of life that is inescapable?”

Cabrera:

“The thesis of moral impediment is very important in my philosophy and it helps to understand why my pessimism is, above all, an ethical pessimism, not a hedonistic or sensible pessimism. I am not primarily pessimistic because of suffering, but because it is impossible to be moral with others and because others cannot be moral with me. My antinatalism is also primarily moral: not to procreate not only to save someone from suffering, but because it creates another morally disabled being, beings who will be structurally incapable of morality.”

It seems as if Cabrera treats morality as the thing that subjects of life should defend instead of the other way around. It is morality that should defend moral subjects. It is individual sentient beings who are morally important, and morality is the conceptual idea that is supposed to defend them. Morality is so important because and only because of the existence of moral subjects, not in itself. As aforesaid, the basic unit of ethics is experience, had no one experienced anything negative, the fact that it is impossible for anyone to be moral with others and that others cannot be moral with anyone, would have been ethically meaningless. Had all the beings in the world been structurally incapable of morality but were also insentient, there would have been no need for morality and there would have been nothing wrong with them being incapable of it. The structural incapability of morality wouldn’t hurt anybody because nobody could get hurt.
The central problem with structural incapability of morality is not ontological one, it is its practical consequences and its implications on the experience level, which are the only things that matter morally. The problem with beings who will be structurally incapable of morality is that they are bound to hurt each other, not that they will hurt morality.

Cabrera’s relation to morality sometimes sounds almost religious, in terms of it having a first cause argument, as if it must exist for its own reasons. But morality is supposed to be a tool for moral subjects to use in order to protect them. It sounds like Kant’s ethics which is so focused on reason as if reason is its own reason. But reason is a tool, a mean, not an end. And so is morality.

Just like ‘humanity’, ‘species’, and ‘nature’, morality is a concept, a notion, a term, not a moral entity in itself. Morality doesn’t care that its implication is impossible. Moral subjects care, because they are the ones who are hurt by the fact that its implication is impossible. And that is a very good reason to never procreate. In my view the most important one. The fact that procreating is necessarily and inevitably creating beings who will be structurally incapable of morality, means that all beings will necessarily and inevitably harm each other.

Cabrera writes that: “in principle, it is not possible to escape moral impediment. As long as you want to continue living, the chances of you falling into moral impediment multiply (including the possibility of procreation).”
Therefore the only way to avoid moral impediment is antinatalism. The impossibility to escape moral impediment is a sufficient reason. If by definition people cannot be moral, and by ‘cannot be moral’ I mean that it is impossible for them not to harm others, then their existence cannot be morally justified.

Question 13:

“if it was possible to completely abolish involuntary suffering in the future, would you still say that procreation is unethical in such a hypothetical future? What hypothetical scenario would convince you to (pro)natalism?”

Cabrera:

“Certainly, I would continue to claim that procreation is immoral in this future world; and here it is clear again why it is convenient to center the argument of the immorality of procreation on manipulation and not on suffering. For even having children in a hypothetical world without suffering, this act would continue to be inevitably manipulative, and therefore immoral. Furthermore, there would still be conflicts between beings without suffering, and boredom and restless desire would be inevitable.”

I fail to see why conflicts between beings without suffering is morally problematic. Problematic to whom? Who is harmed by these conflicts? Is it that the very existence of conflicts is immoral despite that no one is harmed by them? If so, isn’t it to attribute moral status to the conflicts themselves despite that obviously they are not moral entities? Is the conflict between water and rocks immoral?

And given that boredom and restless desire are a sort of suffering, they are not supposed to be included in the hypothetical world described in the question. The whole point is that there would be no suffering in order to isolate the manipulation component in Cabrera’s antinatalsim (if I understand the purpose of the question correctly).

The fact that he would continue to claim that procreation is immoral in this future hypothetical world, despite that no one is harmed in it, goes to show how strange centering the argument of the immorality of procreation on manipulation and not on suffering is. Surly, even in the hypothetical world described in the question, procreation would remain manipulative, but by definition no one is going to be harmed by this manipulation. There would be no victims to this manipulation, and to state that a situation is immoral despite it having no victims is senseless to me.

Nevertheless, this position that I have just expressed is relevant only to a hypothetical world in which suffering was somehow completely abolished, but not to the extremely implausible option of trying to somehow turn our real actual world into a supposedly suffering free world by some advanced technological invention. In that case, I would still argue that procreation is immoral, not because it would remain manipulative as Cabrera argues, but because even if it was plausible, there is no guarantee that someday things wouldn’t change in this world and suffering would come back, and mostly and most importantly because of all the suffering of thousands of trillions of sentient creatures that would be caused while waiting for this extremely implausible option. So to prevent all that I would continue to claim that procreation is immoral. The only thing better than a world that suffering was completely abolished from, is a world that suffering can never come back to.

Cabrera further explains the reasoning of his claim:

“I sustain a structural pessimism about human life, not a mere empirical pessimism of balance between “good things” and “bad things”, with a predominance of “bad things”. This is not my line. In “discomfort and moral impediment” (p.23 onwards), I present a long argumentation about the lack of sensible and moral value of human life based on what I call “terminality of being”, the decaying and frictional being received at birth. As long as this structure is maintained procreation will be immoral.”

I understand that balancing between “good things” and “bad things” is not his line. But it also wasn’t the line of the question. He wasn’t asked whether he would continue to claim that procreation is immoral even if the balancing between “good things” and “bad things” would be in favor of the “good things”, but will he continue to claim that procreation is immoral even if there would be no “bad things” at all. And he gave his answer in the first paragraph. Practically, the scenario given in the question is beyond hypothetical to the point of being absolutely delusional, so obviously it should be taken as a thought experiment only, not a practical suggestion. And under this hypothetical scenario, the whole point is that the structure he describes will not be maintained, “the decaying and frictional being received at birth” is somehow supposed not to negatively affect whom who would live in this future hypothetical world, and so, this can’t be the problem with procreation in this hypothetical world.

Cabrera ends his answer with the following:

“From the pessimistic and antinatalist point of view, we can state that there is no responsible scenario where it is better to be than not to be, no type of being that can compete with the sublime perfection of nothingness.”

Nothingness is not sublime perfection, but literally the absence of all things. There is nothing in nothing by definition, so it can’t be perfect sublime. There are no experiences in nothingness. Non-existence is not worse or better than existence because there is no one there for whom it would be better or worse compared with existence. So it is not better not to be, as no one can not to be, it is just bad to be. Being is harmful and not being is not harmful for the obvious and simple reason that only existing beings can harm others and be harmed, and no one can harm others and be harmed had not existed.

 

You Are So Vain, You Probably Think This World Is About You

Most children would be average and not amazing, incredible, contributive, and meaningful, but that is not the problem with procreation. Obviously the problems are from a different kind and magnitude. However, that fact goes to show how prominent the aspect of vanity in procreation is.

In the text about the Optimism Bias I have mentioned people’s tendency to think that the chances of something bad happening to them are very low and surly below average, and on the contrary that the chances of something good happening to them are very high and surly above average, despite that thought being totally statistically illogical.
The feeling of parents that their children would be amazing, incredible, contributive, and meaningful also doesn’t make any statistical sense. Clearly it is impossible that everyone’s children would be amazing, incredible, contributive, and meaningful. So for people to nevertheless insist on breeding with this premise in mind, they need to think of themselves, or at least of their genes and their parenting abilities, to be potentially amazing, incredible, contributive, and meaningful.

The fact that people have a serious problem with reality testing is not new, and their insistency on creating their own children – as how can they not be as amazing as they are – is extremely conceited.
Even just a bit of rational and realistic speculation would infer that it is most probably the case that people’s children won’t be amazing, incredible and contributive, and that it is not important that they would exist because they would have a positive meaningful impact on the ones who already exist, and that it is so much more likely that they would be just another unnecessary unit of suffering, exploitation and pollution, just another unnecessary entity that needs and therefore takes, harms and being harmed, exploits and being exploited, pollutes and being polluted, in pain and causing pain, bored and boring, meaningless and not meaningful.

And even when every once in a while people with some good potential are somehow being created and somehow are not spoiled by their parents, they are usually spoiled by other means. I’ll let Ernest Becker, which I have referred to two of his books – Escape from Evil and The Denial of Death in the second part of the text about death, explain. This time from Angel in Armor:

“Take the average man who has to stage in his own way the life drama of his own worth and significance. As a youth he, like everyone else, feels that deep down he has a special talent, an indefinable but real something to contribute to the richness and success of life in the universe. But, like almost everyone else, he doesn’t seem to hit on the unfolding of this special something; his life takes on the character of a series of accidents and encounters that carry him along… into new experiences and responsibilities. Career, marriage, family, approaching old age – all these happen to him, he doesn’t command them. instead of his staging the drama of his own significance, he himself is staged, programmed by the standard scenario laid down by his society.”

Nothing about all that is surprising or new and that is because it is so clear that procreation is irrational, sellfish, extremly vain, and x.
But the fact that nothing about any of that is new yet people are still stuck in the same place and without any serious abilty (or even without any serious motivation sadly) to justify their positions and actions regarding procreatrion, at some point needs to renew our approach regarding it. At some point we need to realize that the fact that people are so stuck despite being so wrong, doesn’t mean that we can afford to be stuck depsite being so right. At some point we need to realize that although indeed we are very right, we are living in a very wrong world. And when justice and fairness and ethics have no place because existence itself is structurally unjust, unfair and unethical, we need to seriosuly undermine the structure of existence by other means.

Run Like Hell But Never Reach Heaven

Many people in the world are fully occupied with basic survival. That includes people in the more affluent parts of the world, people who might not need to worry about where their next meal comes from, but are constantly worried about how to pay their next bill. Most people in the world are constantly worried about finding a sufficient and secure income, and then struggle to keep it, and saving as much money as they can so they could someday finally reach the point where they can relax a little bit. And as long as people are in this marathon they rarely stop and think ‘why am I even bothering?’ ‘Is all this so one day I can sit back and not worry about the bills?’ ‘Can it be that the only reward for reaching the finish line is that I can finally stop racing?’

And if that day ever comes at all, it’s usually when people are already too old, tired, worn out, and dispirited to do the things they really want to. And that is if they know what they want to do. Most have no clue, as far as they go they just want to stop running. And that’s why they have been running all these years – so one day they could finally stop. That is absolutely lunatic and dreadful. It is like running a marathon, and not one lasting 42 kilometers but one that lasts almost an entire lifetime, just to experience stop running.

Not running is not really an option in this world. Everybody has to run. Some must run as fast as they possibly can, while others can run much more casually, but everybody needs to run. And tragically, despite that most people run because they want to someday stop, most of them can never stop. Usually it is because they have children to care for, for some it is other family members who need assistance, for others it is health issues, accidents or any other disaster that comes their way and forces them to keep running, and some can’t stop running for psychological reasons such as the feeling that idleness would drive them nuts more than keep running, or because they are so used to running that they have no idea how to stop. And of course many constantly fall on the treadmill, some flat on their faces.

When some people get just comfortable enough to excuse themselves from the daily race for survival, unfortunately only a tiny minority of them manage to think a little bit outside their private race and have renewed observations regarding their pointless run to nowhere, realizing that they are constantly running on a treadmill. Most, for most of their life, have been so occupied with surviving that they are already so deeply immersed in life that it is hard for them to look at it differently.
Seemingly ironically, but also quite obvious, the less immersed people are in their daily survival, the more available they are to reflect over their daily survival. But unfortunately and disappointingly that is very rare. One could expect that many more people, at least at some point, would come to realize how pointless, senseless, devoid and hollow this whole thing is. People with some more time (because they are less occupied with survival) are expected to realize how senseless the survival pursuit is, how pointless, indefinite, vain and circuital it is. To realize that it is as if life has a life of its own, that life is self-moving without the living themselves controlling it or without any external motive or justification. That it exists because it exists.
But that rarely happens. Most people don’t ask themselves why am I even bothering to roll a rock up the hill over and over? Why am I running like hell when I’ll never reach heaven?

However, despite that the vast majority of people don’t seem to bother reflecting over their endless, pointless run to nowhere, and that is obviously very disappointing, the critical argument here is not of the people who keep running. Most of them don’t really have much of a choice but to go on. The criticism is of them throwing others on the treadmill.

I don’t necessarily criticize people for not stop running despite that it is goalless, pointless and senseless, because I understand how hard, if not impossible, it is to stop. I am criticizing them for forcing others to run and partly exactly because it is goalless, pointless and senseless. If you are running because you can’t really stop and not because you really want to reach (or thinking that you can reach) some goal, or because you really believe you have started running out of your own free will and not because otherwise you would fall on your face, why force others onto the same infinite treadmill fraught with difficulties and dangers?
The people who have been thrown onto the infinite treadmill fraught with difficulties and dangers are stuck on it, it is not their fault that they are on it. But it is definitely their fault if they decide to throw others on it as well.

The fact that most people are too occupied with surviving and so are way too deeply immersed in life to find the time to reflect on it, and the fact that out of the few who can find the time to reflect on life very few ever bother to do so, and the fact that out of the few who do so very few are reflecting on what they are condemning their children with, is very conclusive about the chances of people ever deciding not to force more and more people on the infinite treadmill fraught with difficulties and dangers. Therefore the only way to make them stop is not by trying to convince them not to force others onto the infinite treadmill fraught with difficulties and dangers, but by somehow cutting the power.

The Certainty of Thousands of Lifetimes

Although Rivka Weinberg doesn’t discuss the ‘environmental’, the so called ‘misanthropic’, and the ‘harm to other people’ arguments for Antinatalism in her book The Risk of a Lifetime, which I have addressed in the former couple of texts, she did shortly address them during an interview in the Exploring Antinatalism podcast, and what she said about these three arguments can’t be ignored. So the following is not really a supplement to the critical review of her book, but more of a totally independent critical review and a direct reply to her comments about these three arguments.

Regarding the Environmental Argument (01:30:00)

Rivka Weinberg was asked to comment about environmental antinatalism and said:
“Some people say that because the world is overpopulated and we have a climate crisis no one should have any children because that’s like using too many resources and contributing to the problem. I think that is a too high cost to apply to individuals and the benefit is too low. We need to solve the climate crisis but the way to solve that is with institutions and corporations. Not having children will not help at all. This is not the problem. This problem needs to be solved at a government and institutional level. Individuals can only work by getting their government to pass laws. We need different standards for cars, we need public transportation, we need all kinds of green technology, that’s what we need, that’s what is going to solve the problem. Changing our economic ways of life, our carbon dependence. Deciding not to have a child will deprive the individual of their meaningful life shaping relationships and for a benefit that will be very small in terms of the environmental problem.”

I don’t consider myself as environmental antinatalist, and as explained in the post about the Voluntary Human Extinction Movement, I don’t share the same arguments or motive for human extinction as VHEMT. However, that is absolutely not because I think that the solution to environmental problems is different standards for cars, public transportation, all kinds of green technology, not to mention the most ridiculously absurd suggestion – institutions and corporations, which are obviously exactly the ones who are most responsible for most of the harm (with corporations having exactly zero motivation to solve problems which don’t affect their financial gain), but because I don’t consider the environment as a moral patient. The environment, ecological systems, species, and similar abstract terms often ascribed to the environmental argument, are not entities and therefore don’t hold any moral status. Their moral relevancy is only instrumental, not intrinsic, meaning they are important only because they are important to sentient creatures who are harmed when these are affected. I think that people must stop creating new people because each person severely harms numerous other sentient creatures, not because humanity affects the insentient environment.

But since numerous sentient creatures live in ecological systems, and therefore are hurt by what is referred to as environmental problems, indirectly, I highly sympathize with the ‘environmental argument’ for antinatalism, only that I consider it as part of the harm to others argument.

Anyway, I find Weinberg’s response to the environmental argument a case of lack of knowledge, and speciesism. Her claim demonstrates considerable ignorance regarding the harms caused by humanity overall, as well as on the individual level. She claims that the benefit of not having a child will be very small in terms of the climate crisis, however, researchers from Lund University in Sweden found that avoiding having a child can save an average of 58.6 tonnes of CO2-equivalent emissions per year. And according to a study by statisticians at Oregon State University, the carbon legacy and greenhouse gas impact of an extra child in the United States is almost 20 times more important than some of the other environment-friendly practices people might employ during their entire lives such as driving a high mileage car, recycling, or using energy-efficient appliances and light bulbs.

And according to another study called Global Demographic Trends and Future Carbon Emissions, from more than a decade ago, meaning its conclusions are known for more than a decade now, reducing fertility rates so as to match the UN’s ‘low fertility’ projections rather than the ‘medium fertility’ projections, which corresponds to an average difference of 0.5 children per breeder, would likely result in a yearly reduction in GHG emissions of 5.1 billion tons of carbon by 2100. 5.1 billion tons per year is more than five times the annual emissions savings we would achieve in 50 years by doubling the fuel efficiency of the world auto fleet, or by halving the average kilometers traveled per car, or by tripling the number of nuclear reactors currently providing electricity around the world, or by increasing current wind energy capacity 50 times, or by halting all deforestation everywhere around the world. Reducing population growth could provide more emissions reductions than all five of these other measures put together.
The study’s authors estimate that following the low rather than the medium fertility projections would account for “between 16% and 29% of required emissions reductions by 2050.

Besides its severe carbon footprint, breeding is also an act of plundering, as each procreation further enhances robbing resources from others. One of these resources is water and people use a lot of it, even for things we rarely think of in that context. For example, it takes more than 33 liters of water to produce just one of the chips that typically power smart phones, laptops and iPads. A single smartphone requires 240 gallons of water to produce. And it even goes further than that as every bit and byte people consume over the internet has an indirect cost in terms of water waste due to the enormous cooling demand in data centers. In fact, even when people drink bottled water they are highly water wasteful, as it takes about 4 liters of water to produce one liter plastic bottle of water.

The harmfulness of bottled water is not only their wastefulness but mostly their pollution.
A million plastic bottles are bought around the world every minute. Less than half of the bottles are collected for recycling and less than 10% of those collected are turned into new bottles. Most plastic bottles end up in landfill or in the ocean.

And bottles are only part of the enormous plastic pollution. It is estimated that more than a trillion plastic bags are used worldwide annually. Only 1% of plastic bags are returned for recycling. Americans throw away 100 billion plastic bags annually. That’s about 307 bags per person! The average person produces half a pound of plastic waste of all kinds every day.
Weinberg may suggest that plastic should be outlawed but this is extremely unlikely to ever happen. The current course is the opposite as plastic production is expected to double in the next 20 years and quadruple by 2050.

And of course it is not just plastic. An average American consumes about 45,000 pounds of metal (through the consumption of various products) during a lifetime. Each pound of metal must be mined, processed, transported and manufactured into consumable products, all stages are considerably polluting. For example, currently, about 25,500 tons of silver are consumed every year. There is some of it in every car, computer and phone, as well as many other products.
Humanity as a whole throws about 100 million aluminum and steel cans every day.
And in general, each person sends about 64 tons of waste to landfills over a lifetime.
Some of this waste can theoretically be reduced, but practically so far it has only been increased. And other forms of waste can’t be reduced. For example every day each person produces about 20 gallons of sewage. Over a lifetime, that is 567,575 gallons. Billions of creatures must live with all this human shit. Of course it would be better for them if there is less of it, and there would be less shit if there are less people.

If humanity is not only very far from ending the plastic age but its catastrophe is only getting worse and worse, despite that it is a very recent technology and despite that its immense and irreversible damage is well known for decades, how likely is it to ever end the rest of the polluting industries?

Since as opposed to the common way people present it, procreation is not having a baby but creating a person, I have focused here on harms people commonly cause throughout their lifetime, and not particularly when they are babies. However it is impossible not to specifically refer to the harm of disposable diapers, mainly in terms of non-degradable waste, and the pollution during the production phase.
The number of diapers babies are using depends on when they are starting to regularly use the toilet. On average, most children are potty trained by around 35 to 39 months of age. Considering that in the first year of life, babies are using about 3,000 diapers, and in the second year between 1,500 and 2,000, the estimations are that each baby adds about 6,000 diapers to landfills, where they will not compost or biodegrade.

People can choose to use cloth diapers instead of disposable ones, but they don’t. About 95 percent of American parents choose disposable diapers over reusable ones.
But even if more people would choose reusable diapers, that option also has a very high environmental impact due to cotton production, which is one of the highest in terms of pesticide use, as well as the energy and water costs of laundering cloth diapers. A life-cycle analysis, conducted by the Environment Agency in the UK, compared the manufacturing, disposal, and energy costs of both diaper types and found that based on average laundry habits and appliance efficiency, the overall carbon emissions created by cloth diapering were roughly the same as those of using disposables.

Another significant harm involved in laundry, and with every other way people are cleaning their things and themselves, is the use of cleansing agents. Detergents can have poisonous effects on all types of aquatic life when present in high quantities, and this includes the biodegradable detergents. All detergents destroy the external mucus layers that protect the fish from bacteria and parasites, plus they can cause severe damage to the gills. People are harming other sentient creatures even when they clean their dishes, their clothes, and themselves.

Again, there is no reason to focus on infancy when reviewing the harms of people, but again, it is hard to ignore the particular contribution of the harms of detergents during infancy, especially ones involved in laundry, as babies requires a lot of it. The few people who do choose to use reusable diapers need to wash them, and everyone need to wash their baby’s clothes, sheets, blankets, bibs, sleepers, socks, pants and etc., and many other things that babies tend to spit up on, drool on, or any other way make dirty. That adds up to a lot of detergents use, and since the severe harm that each use of each detergent doesn’t even cross the minds of the vast majority of people, they don’t even bother using at least the little bit less harmful options, not to mention using natural alternatives such baking soda, lemon, vinegar and etc. The vast majority of people are using conventional detergents which most are made of petroleum, are nonbiodegradable, contain various damaging chemicals including carcinogen ones, and phosphates which build up in rivers and lakes causing hypoxia (low oxygen) due to algal bloom.

Some call this very very partial list of examples – ‘harming the environment’, as if the environment is the one who gets hurt. But it is not the environment, it is the trillions upon trillions of creatures living in it who are severely harmed by everything that people are doing.
And so I agree with Weinberg that it is “a too high cost to apply to individuals and the benefit is too low”, only exactly from the opposite direction. The cost of procreation is way too high to apply to innumerous individual sentient creatures, and the benefit to people who want to procreate is way too low.
When considering humanity’s massive harm not to the sustainability of ecosystems which are not moral entities, but to trillions of their inhabitants, who most definitely are moral entities, I fail to see how it is not wrong for humans to procreate.

Not only that people have never considered changing their economic ways of life, and their carbon dependence, they have so far done the opposite. Even during major economic crises, wars, famines, natural disasters, extreme poverty and etc., people have never seriously considered changing their way of life, so why would they stop now?

The 2008 financial crisis has brought the Occupy Movement with the famous slogan “We are the 99%”, but unfortunately, quantitatively they were less than 1%. Most of the public, in the United States and outside of it, as always, remained silent, submissive, conformist and passive.
And if people are not changing the world for their own sake, what are the odds that they would do it allegedly for the world’s sake? If people are not doing it for themselves, considering that many climate change effects have already affected many of them in the past decades, what are the odds that they would do it for the ‘environment’, all the more so while they have systematically destroyed it all along history? Or for the sake of other animals, all the more so while they are still refusing to stop creating billions of them every year only to exploit while severely torturing them all their horrible lives in the food industry?

There is no way that people would ever change their ways even when they are the ones who directly pay the price, and it is definitely not going to happen when it is other people who will pay the price, and most definitely not when it is other animals.

Regarding The Misanthropic Argument (01:33:00)

Rivka Weinberg was asked to comment about David Benater’s misanthropic argument which was presented as follows – every human being causes vast amounts of harm to other sentient beings including harm to nonhuman beings. Becoming fully aware of the extent of the harm we do, could possibly threaten the meaning in life.
And she replied that “most people are not terrible but if they are raised in a loving and stable environment are very unterrible. And so I think that there is no reason to not procreate because your child is going to be terrible. I think that if you are going to be nice to your child the likelihood of that child to be terrible is very low. So I don’t think that that aspect of the argument works at all. I think most people are not terrible and the people who are terrible are usually raised with a lot of cruelty, usually. So if you are going to have a child and you’ll raise it in a loving and a nice way I don’t think they are going to be a terrible person. I think that the likelihood of that are very low and I think that percentage of people that are awful is also small. Most people are regular, not heroic, not cruel, they are regular people. And they are not so bad that we have to make sure not to have them. In terms of our effect on other creatures of the world, I think we have other ways to respond to this than to say that we need to stop existing. We can have more respect for other animals, we can give them more of their habitat, we can do other reforms to be less damaging to other sentient species.”

Weinberg is absolutely totally wrong about people. They are absolutely totally terrible. It is very hard to accurately assess how terrible each person is since it depends on various factors such as location, socioeconomic status, consumption habits, life expectancy, livelihood, diet and etc., however, regardless of any circumstances, being terrible to numerous others is inevitable. And the most immediate and prominent harm is caused by what people eat.

Every person has to eat, and every food has a price. Unfortunately, most people are choosing the ones with the highest price – animal based foods. Therefore in most cases procreating is choosing that more fish would suffocate to death by being violently sucked out of water, that more chickens would be cramped into tiny cages with each forced to live in a space the size of an A4 paper, that more calves would be separated from their mothers, and more cow mothers would be left traumatized by the abduction of their babies, that more pigs would suffer from chronic pain, it is choosing more lame sheep, more beaten goats, more turkeys who can barely stand as a result of their unproportionate bodies, more ducks who are forced to live out of water and in filthy crowded sheds, more rabbits imprisoned in an iron cage the size of their bodies, more geese being aggressively plucked, more male chicks being gassed, crushed or suffocated since they are unexploitable for eggs nor meat, more snakes being skinned alive, and more crocodiles and alligators being hammered to death and often also skinned alive to be worn, and more mice, cats, dogs, fish, rabbits, and monkeys being horrifically experimented on.

Each person directly consumes thousands of animals. More accurate average figures are varied according to each person location. An average American meat eater for example consumes more than 2,020 chickens, about 1,700 fish, more than 70 turkeys, more than 30 pigs and sheep, about 11 cows, and tens of thousands of aquatic animals, some directly and some indirectly (as many of which are fed to other consumed animals).
American meat eaters are ranked as one of the highest per person meat consumers in the world, and so these figures are higher than the world average. On the other hand, most of the people who consume relatively little animal based foods, would choose otherwise if they could. The only reason they don’t is because they can’t afford it. Time and again it is shown that as soon as people’s financial status improves, one of the first things they do is increase their animal based food consumption. Economic improvement is always accompanied by an increase in meat consumption. Per capita meat consumption has been growing persistently everywhere in the world. Among low-income societies it doubled in the last 20 years, and in what is referred to as “middle income” societies it tripled in the last couple of decades. So the consumption gaps are narrowing, and more and more animals are being harmed by more and more people.

Weinberg could have suggested that considering the vast amounts of harm to other sentient beings by consuming animal products, including the vast environmental harm of animal farming (a claim which could have also supported her reply to the former question), people must raise their children as vegans. But she is too speciesist and too ignorant regarding, first and foremost the torture, and also the environmental effect of factory farms to suggest that. And even if she did, obviously there is no way to insure that children would stay vegan for life, and veganism, as preferable as it is over animal based food, is still extremely harmful towards other sentient beings.

Factory farming is the worst and cruelest way people feed themselves. But it is not that other options are harmless. It is impossible to eat without harming someone, somewhere along the line. And it takes a very long line to make food, any food. Much longer, and much more harmful than people tend to think.

Each agricultural area was once the living space of other creatures, who were killed, chased away, starved (as people have destroyed their food sources), dried (as people took control of their water sources), being exposed to predator (as people have destroyed their dens and other hiding places), restricted by fences, polluted by chemicals people constantly spray, and even burned alive during slash-and-burn.
And all this is not an historical description of how agriculture has started, it all still happens all the time. Billions of animals are constantly being poisoned, starved, dehydrated, chased away, polluted, trampled by tractors, combines, ploughs and harvesters, their homes are being destroyed and etc. All are common harms inherent to agriculture, and happening every single moment.

The most direct and immediate harm of plant based agriculture is the spread of poisons such as pesticides, herbicides, insecticides and fungicides. More than 2.5 million tons of poisons are spread all over the world every year. Each gram is aimed to kill any creature in the area, and any potentially “competitive” plant in the area. Much of these poisons also harm creatures living far from the originally sprayed farms, as chemicals tend to drift by wind and are washed by rain. The estimation is that almost 100 million fish and birds are poisoned to death each year by pesticides, and about a billion are harmed by it.

Another type of chemicals intensively used in agriculture which are also harmful, are fertilizers. Most fertilizers are synthetic, but some, mainly in organic farms, are made of animals’ bones, blood, feathers and of course manure. Obviously none of which are originated from wild animals who died naturally, but from factory farmed animals who were tortured and murdered. So anyone who wants to avoid the harms of synthetic fertilizers, is bound to support the use of animal based ones, and so indirectly subsidize factory farming by making animals exploitation more profitable.

Although most of the trees in the rainforests are cut for cattle grazing, a very considerable amount is being cut for growing some of the most basic foods that vegans are consuming such as nuts, sugar, tea, coffee, several types of fruits and vegetables, and even the most common raw material for most of people’s clothes – cotton.

Meat is notoriously water wasteful, but the production of many vegetables also requires plenty of water. According to the Institute of Mechanical Engineers it takes 17,196 liters of water to produce 1kg of chocolate, 3,025 liters to produce 1kg of olives, 2, 497 liters to produce 1kg of rice, about the same amount for 1kg of cotton, 1,849 liters to produce 1kg of dry pasta, 1,608 liters to produce 1kg of bread, 822 liters to produce 1kg of apples, 790 liters to produce 1kg of bananas, and 287 liters to produce 1kg of potatoes. Humans’ excessive use of water leaves entire regions dried, and all the beings living there are left to dehydrate.

A lot of water is also being used after the cultivation stage. The production of food requires a lot of water for washing, cooking, boiling, cooling industrial machinery and etc. But probably the most harmful aspect of food processing is energy, which is obviously inherent to each and every part along the process of each and every food item. Almost each and every food item goes through several processing stages. Many require removal of unwanted parts, cleaning, grinding, liquefaction, drying, sorting, coating, supplementation of other ingredients, cooling, heating, baking, steaming, freezing and etc. All stages are energy-intensive, and the vast majority of it comes from fossil fuels.

Alternative energy sources other than fossil fuels are also harmful. For example, hydraulic dams dehydrate entire habitats, wind turbines are killing many birds, and solar panels are composed of heavy metals. But they are still less harmful than fossil fuels, yet humans, as usual, choose the most harmful option. And since there is little control over the chosen energy production method used for each food item, people are bound to take part in severe harms to other creatures. They can’t even really choose the least harmful method, and certainly can’t choose a harmless one, as there is no such thing. And even if it was possible to choose such an option, since most people care so little about harms to others they would probably simply choose the cheapest one.

Another stage in food production that is responsible for a lot of energy consumption (maybe even the most) is food transportation. Each and every country is highly depended on long-distance food, so everyone, everywhere, participates in a global food system.
Some foods travel thousands of miles during the process stage only, before they are sent all over the world as export. It is very difficult to accurately calculate the mileage of each food item since many foods are composed of several ingredients which each has travelled long distances as well. From the field to the first processing stage, then to the next processing stages, then to the packhouse, then to the storage warehouse, and only then to the airport or harbour. All that is for each ingredient, of each final food item.

All the harms involved in animal based food can theoretically be avoided if all humans would decide to go vegan. But that’s not going to happen. And anyway, not all the harms involved in plant based food can be avoided. Avoiding all food items that cause air pollution, water pollution, noise pollution, climate alteration, land alteration, land clearing, land destruction, trampling, water waste, poisoning and etc., is simply impossible.

There are some people, a tiny minority unfortunately, that try to minimize their harm level by being vegan and environmentally aware, and take part in positive and meaningful activism, but even these few people are forced to do some terrible things to others simply by living in a world such as ours, where no one can avoid harming others even if they really try. And of course these are the least terrible people in the world, people who are trying not to be terrible but have no choice. The vast majority of people, the regular people, simply choose to be terrible.

So the likelihood of people being terrible is not very low but is actually guaranteed, and the percentage of people that are awful is not small but in fact close to 100%.
She is right that most people are regular, but only because the norm is cruelty and indifference. Our world is so terrible that regular people are cruel.

Weiberg had another thing to say about the misanthropic argument:

“The other thing I would say about this, is let’s say that it turns out that we killing off, just our very existence kills of a certain species of another species of fish, we excel things and they die. So now it is a question, who should go extinct me or the fish? Why should I pick the fish? Why can’ I pick me?  That is another problem with the misanthropic argument, that I don’t think I should sacrifice myself for another species.”

Weinberg presents the issue as if humanity and a certain species of fish are simply two species living in the world, and so there is no reason for her as a human to prefer the fish over herself. But as opposed to fish, humans live as masters of the universe, not as just another species. Their dominance and harmfulness is unprecedented. There is no other species that is even remotely as harmful as humans. Surly, many lifeforms eat other lifeforms, but no other lifeform is imprisoning other lifeforms for their entire lives. No other lifeform totally shatters other lifeforms’ social lives. No other lifeform prevents clean air, clean water, and natural environment. No other lifeform prevents access to natural food. No other lifeform is constantly genetically modifying other lifeforms to extract more meat, milk, eggs, skin, wool, feathers, fur and etc., from other lifeforms. No other lifeform castrates other lifeforms. No other lifeform burns numbers on other lifeforms. No other lifeform cuts the horns, tails and teeth of other lifeforms. No other lifeform rides, chains, and enslaves other lifeforms. No other lifeform forces other lifeforms to dance, do tricks, to dress up, to jump fences, to fight each other. No other lifeform experiments on other lifeforms.
To compare mankind with any other kind in terms of harm is absolutely ridiculous. And can be done only by an extremely ignorant and speciesist person.

Humans have an extremely high harm toll which makes supporting their right to exist a support in the violation of the rights of anyone who is hurt by them.

Weinberg presents the claim as if it is one human individual against one nonhuman individual and as if the misanthropic argument is choosing to favor the nonhuman, while practically it is one human individual against ten thousands of nonhuman individuals. As earlier mentioned, it is very hard to estimate the harm each human is causing to other creatures but in any case it is an enormous one under all circumstances (such as different lifestyles), as humans are making the lives of many animals very miserable in many ways.

I call to stop all human procreation not in the name of ecosystems, or since humans deserve to go extinct, or because I think it would solve all the problems in the world, but because of the harm to trillions of sentient victims per year.
Every day the human race provides us with more and more reasons why it must be stopped. And every day it provides us with less and less reasons to believe it would ever happen voluntarily. For it to finally happen, we must make it happen.

Regarding the Harms to Other People (01:36:00)

Rivka Weinberg was asked: what about the harms we do to others using technology and exploitation of other people?
And she replied: “we need laws and regulations. Not having a child is not going to solve anything. You still going to have this exploitation, so if you wanna solve exploitation work to create laws that reduce that like minimum wages, and different kinds of trade agreements. It is our political institutions that will solve the problem, I don’t think that going extinct is necessary to solve this problem. It is also not practical, you are not going to have a child, but somebody else will and all the problems that you thought you are solving will go on.”

Human exploitation is way too beneficial to the exploiters for them to be deterred by laws and regulations. And in many cases human exploitation is also way too beneficial for the law makers and regulators for them to legislate such laws in the first place, and to later enforce them and to regulate exploitive industries. Even in cases where corporations don’t bribe law makers, they always have a strong lobby and other ways to influence relevant officials, while exploited people almost never have a voice. Corporations bringing in foreign currency to poor countries are way more beneficial for local politicians than their domestic population so they are always the last in line of priorities. That’s why despite that child labor and slavery are forbidden all over the world, both are still very prevalent all over the world.

Local governments don’t have a strong interest in fighting the exploitation of their own people since in many cases exploitative industries represent most of these countries’ export revenue and since their economies are highly depended on these industries. This is usually the economic and social background which corporations are seeking in the first place when they are looking for ‘sights’ to invest in. In the eyes of the corporations, the country is better for business, when the people are poorer, the lands are richer in terms of desirable resources, and the officials are easily bribed.
For example, it is well known for decades now that about three quarters of the chocolate industry relies on cacao from countries where child labor is extremely common. Laws and regulations didn’t and will not change that partly because people care much more about buying cheap chocolate than not supporting slavery and child labor. Many have seen the reports and documentary films about the miserable lives of poor kids, mainly from West Africa, in the cacao plantations – where they are forced to work extremely hard for extremely long hours, are beaten if they try to escape or even for working ‘too slowly’, have poor sanitation and no clean water – but are still consuming chocolate according to their taste or its price, and regardless of the living conditions of the people who have produced it for them (and have never in their life tasted it).

A very similar story occurs in the cobalt mining industry which also involves slavery and child labor, and often both. Yet many people buy a new phone every couple of years, so not to stay behind in terms of the cutting edge luxurious technology, while indifferently leaving the poorest people in the world way behind in terms of the most basic living conditions, including clean water, proper nutrition and sanitation and hygiene.

Unfortunately, prostitution is practically legal or limitedly legal in most of the countries in the world. But sex trafficking is formally forbidden in all of them. Yet human trafficking, which most of it involves the sex industry, is the largest international crime system after arms trade and drug traffic. Despite being illegal and extremely harmful, all three industries are thriving all around the world.
Like in any other example, laws and regulations will not solve the problem which is too systematical and ingrained in human culture, and social and economic structure. People don’t need a regulative reform but a radical social and cultural revolution in the way they view others, and in the economic system which actively encourages such extreme inequality and poverty that people can buy other people, rent other people, and many parents sell their own children to the sex industry in order to pay for their debts. Many of these children, along with other children who are kidnaped by traffickers, or end up in the sex industry after running away from home and it was the only available option for them to support themselves, would never escape this industry. That is millions of children all around the world.

The problem is way too systematical for laws and regulations to solve it. Child labor is illegal in most of the world yet it is estimated that 1 in 10 children across the globe are subjected to child labor, with almost half of them (about 75 million children), being in hazardous forms of work. The problem is way more systematical than that.

Corporations are interested in increasing profits only. That’s what they are about. They can do that by increasing the prices of their products, and by that risking that consumers would buy products from their competitors, or they can decrease the expenses, which obviously never means decreasing their own salaries but usually the salaries of the ones who already earn the least, and in the case of sweatshops, of the ones who are already extremely poor and have no other option but working in extremely exploitive, unsafe and unhealthy jobs.

Laws and regulations will not provide the so demandable change in the case of sweatshops as well. Partly it is because as long as people in the richer world are indifferent enough, people in the poorer world are desperate enough, politicians and officials are corruptible enough, and corporations are greedy enough, nothing will ever change.

Most sweatshop workers earn less than their daily living costs, and their only other option to support themselves and their families is another sweatshop with the same exploitive conditions. Tens if not hundreds of millions of people are trapped in this system of exploitation, which is hardly likely to ever change by laws and regulations.

There is nothing new about any of this, not to you, not to the common consumer, not to the chocolate industry, not the technology industry, not the sex industry, not the fashion industry, and not to law makers and regulators.
Exploitation exists for thousands of years now. It wasn’t even reduced but has actually evolved in terms of the number of exploited people, the exploitation methods, the exploited age, their ethnical diversity, and their global spread. The fact that it evolved and is still evolving all the time is an indication that it is here to stay, and that laws and regulations are definitely not the answer.

Exploitation of people is not a result of lack of laws and regulations. It is way too easy to throw that as a solution. The problem is much deeper than that. The problem is global and systematic, not local and regulative. Human exploitation is mostly the result of a global economic system designed to favor the richer at the expense of the poorer. It is originated from the fact that more than half of the people in the world are poor and about a third are in deep poverty, not because there are no laws and regulations in some places around the world. The problem is global since the workforce had turned global a long time ago and so people are consuming products that are produced all over the world, and mostly in the poorest areas of the world, since in these places people are so poor that they will work for the lowest salary possible.
The only reason I am bothering you with such basic facts about globalization and capitalism,  which I am sure you are all very familiar with, is since Weinberg chose to avoid a very serious and relevant question by hiding behind the notorious ‘we need laws and regulations’. Of course we need better laws and regulations, but laws and regulations are not, never have, and never will be determined by what is right for the common people, and are always a product of the interests of the tiny most powerful minority. The issue of human exploitation is way too systematical, historical, common, established and complex to seriously suggest laws and regulations as the solution. And in this case, it is more than a tiny minority that benefits from this situation. Many people benefit from the current state of affairs, and these are the common consumers who can get more of the stuff they like, and cheaply. And if most people feel that they are benefiting from the global exploitation, they are not very likely to support more laws and regulations.

There are already laws and regulations against slavery yet it is still common all around the world in one form or another. It is not formal and explicit as it was when it was legal, but people still own other people. They may not buy people in auctions like they used to up until about 200 years ago in most of the world, but many people, in fact more than there were about 200 years ago, are trapped in all kinds of social and economic entanglements that have made them practically enslaved.

Many people around the world are engaged in forced labor (also called involuntary servitude) which is basically situations in which people are bound to work against their will, because of structural reasons such as poverty, wars, droughts, social discrimination, migration, corruption, high rates of unemployment, crime and etc., not because of legal and regulative reasons. And so laws and regulations will not solve most of the types of human exploitation even if humanity took that issue seriously, and currently we are not even there yet.

There is no reason to believe that things that have so far not been solved, and many of which have even gotten worse, will ever be solved.

It is beyond naïve to seriously suggest that political institutions will solve the problem, while they have so far all along history mostly been a huge part of the problem or were totally incompetent in solving it.

It seems that Weinberg chooses to believe that absence of laws and regulations is the source of the problem, and also the greed and cruelty of a tiny minority of people. But the truth is that the origin is corrupted, perverted, inequitable, unfair, discriminative and unjust social, cultural and mostly economic systems, and also the absence of care and the greed of the vast majority of the human population.

And even if she was right, why should people suffer until the values reverse? Until their welfare becomes prior to others’ profits? Even if the priorities could someday change for the better, how is it permissible to procreate before they do? How is it ethically permissible to contribute to such a dire situation instead of changing it first? How is it ethically permissible to create a person who will be bound to take part in the exploitation of others, on a daily basis, because theoretically the solution is laws and regulations?

And these questions also directly relate to the last part in her comment: “It is also not practical, you are not going to have a child, but somebody else will and all the problems that you thought you are solving will go on.”
That is a very strange argument from someone who explicitly bases her principles of procreative permissibility on a Kantian framework. An ethical prohibition is not supposed to be personally optional but universally obligatory, especially under a Kantian framework. If an argument is valid, it is supposed to apply to everyone, so somebody else is also not supposed to have a child. Ethics is not supposed to be determined by how plausible it is that other people would apply its valid conclusions. If avoiding harming others is a valid argument and if everyone is bound to harm others, then no one should be permitted to procreate.

Of course some people, probably most, would choose not to be ethical and to be selfish and indifferent towards harming others, but that is not a justified reason to permit them to be unethical.
Unfortunately I agree that people would never be ethical, not in general and definitely not in relation to procreation specifically, but that doesn’t mean that antinatalism isn’t right and so we should permit people to procreate, but that antinatalism isn’t applicable and so we must look for other ways to stop people from procreating.

References

  1. org/slavery-today/modern-slavery
  2. Ash, M.; Livezey, J. and Dohlman, E. (2006). Soybean backgrounder. USDA: Economic Research Service. Retrieved from United States Department of Agriculture
  3. org/news/will-wind-turbines-ever-be-safe-birds
  4. com/news/av/stories-43699464/i-m-not-having-children-because-i-want-to-save-the-planet
  5. com/news/science-environment-36492596
  6. Biomass use, production, feed efficiencies, and greenhouse gas emissions from global livestock systems. PNAS, 110, 52
  7. Brian C. O’Neill, et al., “Global Demographic Trends and Future Carbon Emissions,” PNAS 107 (2010)
  8. com/science/light-pollution
  9. Budolfson Bryant Mark Consumer Ethics, Harm Footprints, And The Empirical Dimensions Of Food Choices 2015
  10. com
  11. ChartsBin statistics collector team (2013). Current worldwide annual meat consumption per capita Viewed 29 February 2016 from ChartsBin
  12. org.uk/media/5235306/The-life-of-Broiler-chickens.pdf
  13. com/blog/pollutants-in-laundry-detergent
  14. container-recycling.org/index.php
  15. com/a-child-raised-to-weigh-five-hundred-pounds-by-age-ten
  16. com/the-fish-we-kill-to-feed-the-fish-we-eat
  17. com/the-forgotten-mothers-of-chickens-we-eat
  18. countries and production systems. Water Resources and Industry, 1-2, 25-36.
  19. com
  20. org
  21. Deborah Netburn3 billion tons of food being wasted each year. Can we stop it? August 30, 2019
  22. com/u/ecowatch
  23. encyclopedie-environnement.org/app/pdf?idpost=6884&idauthor=A-38&urlimg=%2Fapp%2Fuploads%2F2016%2F10%2Fpollution-lumineuse_couverture.jpg
  24. nsw.gov.au/wastegrants/organics-infrastructure.htm
  • Ercin A.E., Aldaya M.M. and Hoekstra A.Y. (2012). The water footprint of soy milk and soy burger and equivalent animal products. Ecological equivalent animal products. Ecological Indicators, 18, 392-402
  1. Eshel G., Shepon A., Makow T. and Milo R. (2014). Land, irrigation water, greenhouse gas, and reactive nitrogen burdens of meat, eggs, and dairy production in the United States. PNAS, 111, 33, 11996-12001
  2. FAO Save Food Global Food Waste and Loss Initiative
  • fao.org/food-loss-and-food-waste/en
  1. org/zhc/detail-events/en/c/889172
  2. Food and Agriculture Organisation of the United Nations Statistics Division 2014. Retrieved 23 February 2016 from FAO Stat
  3. Food, the Environment, and Global Justice 2017 by Mark Bryant Budolfson
  4. FoodBank Hunger Report 2018
  • com
  1. com/sites/jimhenry/2016/11/26/millions-more-cars-on-the-road-and-not-just-for-thanksgiving
  2. org/article/214/stress-on-the-environment-society-and-resources
  3. Good K. (2014). The surprising way your diet can fix the soy and deforestation problem. One Green Planet. Retrieved from One Green Planet
  4. com/guides/the-high-cost-of-the-food-superhighway
  5. Herrero M., Havlíkb P., Valinc H., Notenbaertb A., Rufinob M.C., Thorntond P.K., Blümmelb M., Weissc F., Graceb D. and Obersteinerc, M. (2013)
  6. Hoekstra A.Y. (2012). The hidden water resource use behind meat and dairy. Animal Frontiers, 2, 2
  7. Hoekstra and Chapagain, 2008, cited in Ercin A.E., Aldaya M.M. and Hoekstra A.Y. (2012). The water footprint of soy milk and soy burger and equivalent animal products. Ecological Indicators, 18, 392-402
  8. co.uk/life-style/food-and-drink/veganism-environment-veganuary-friendly-food-diet-damage-hodmedods-protein-crops-jack-monroe-a8177541.html
  9. co.uk/news/science/environment-extinction-elephant-giraffe-rhino-hippo-biodiversity-animal-history-a8859746.html
  10. International Dark-Sky Association. “International Dark Sky Places.” Accessed November 19, 2013. darksky.org/night-sky-conservation/34-ida/about-ida/142-idsplaces
  11. Karstensen J., Peters G.P., and Andrew R.M. (2013). Attribution of CO2 emissions from Brazilian deforestation to consumers between 1990 and 2010 Environmental Research Letters, 8
  12. Lighting Research Center. Light Pollution. Accessed November 19, 2013
  13. rpi.edu/programs/nlpip/lightinganswers/lightpollution/abstract.asp
  14. Mekonnen M.M. and Hoekstra A.Y. (2012). A global assessment of the water footprint of farm animal products. Ecosystems, 15, 401-415. DOI:10.1007/s10021-011-9517-8
  15. org
  16. National Soybean Research Laboratory NSRL. Benefits of soy. Retrieved from: NSRL.
  17. com/magazine/2018/06/plastic-planet-waste-pollution-trash-crisis/
  18. One Green Planet (2012). Facts on animal farming and the environment. Retrieved from One Green Planet.
  19. org
  20. Paul A. Murtaugh and Michael G. Schlax, “Reproduction and the Carbon Legacies of Individuals,” Global Environmental Change 19 (2009): 14-20, p. 18, Table 3 (“Optimistic Scenario”)
  21. org/issues/animals-used-for-food/factory-farming
  22. Piazza J., Ruby M.B., Loughnan S., Luong M., Kulik J., Watkins H.M. and Seigerman M. (2015). Rationalizing meat consumption. The 4Ns. Appetite, 91, 114-128
  23. Pimentel D., Houser J., Preiss E., White O., Fang H., Mesnick L., Barsky T., Tariche S., Schreck J. and Alpert S. (1997). Water resources:Agriculture, the environment, and society. BioScience, 47, 2, 97-106
  24. org
  25. com/food-miles
  26. Smil V. (2014). Eating meat: Constants and changes. Global Food Security, 3, 2, 67-71 dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.gfs.2014.06.001
  27. com/smart-news/how-many-birds-do-wind-turbines-really-kill-180948154
  28. Steinfeld H., Gerber P., Wassenaar T., Castel V., Rosales M. and de Haan, C. (2006). Livestock’s Long Shadow: Environmental issues and options. Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations. Rome, Italy. Retrieved from FAO
  29. org/children-climate-change-save-planet
  30. Sustainability of meat-based and plant-based diets and the environment by David Pimentel and Marcia Pimentel the Department of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY
  31. com/born-to-die-the-life-of-a-broiler-chicken
  32. The Campaign for Dark Skies. About the Campaign for Dark Skies. Accessed November 19, 2013. britastro.org/dark-skies/about.htm?1O.
  33. The Problems of Light Pollution — Overview
  34. com/environment/2011/jan/12/vegetarians-food-animal-origin-fertiliser-vegetarian
  35. com/environment/2013/jun/30/stephen-emmott-ten-billion
  36. com/environment/2017/jul/12/want-to-fight-climate-change-have-fewer-children
  37. com/environment/2017/jun/28/a-million-a-minute-worlds-plastic-bottle-binge-as-dangerous-as-climate-change
  38. com/green-food/homemade-bone-meal-a-partial-solution-to-peak-phosphate.html
  39. com/green-food/vegan-organic-agriculture-is-your-carrot-really-vegan.html
  40. com/lawn-garden/finally-a-practical-guide-to-dealing-withmanure-book-review.html
  41. com/renewable-energy/north-america-wind-turbines-kill-around-300000-birds-annually-house-cats-around-3000000000.html
  42. UN DESA, World Population Prospects: The 2012 Revision, Key Findings and Advance Tables (New York: United Nations, 2013), pp. 1-2, http://esa.un.org/unpd/wpp/Publications/Files/WPP2012_HIGHLIGHTS.pdf
  43. Watch magazine. Retrieved from Worldwatch Institute
  44. Water Foorptint Netweork
  45. What’s Wrong with Industrial Agriculture Environmental Health Perspectives Volume 110, Number 5, May 2002
  46. World Hunger and Poverty Facts and Statistic 2016
  47. World Watch Magazine, 17, 4. Retrieved from World Watch
  48. Worldwatch Institute (2004). Now, it’s not personal! But like it or not, meat-eating is becoming a problem for everyone on the planet.
  49. WWF (2014). The growth of soy: Impacts and solutions. WWF International. Gland, Switzerland
  50. WWF (n.d). Soy – Facts and Data. Retrieved from WWF
  51. Ziegler L. (2015). Keep showering, California. Just lay off the burgers & nuts. Medium. Retrieved from: Medium
  52. Zonderland-Thomassen M.A. and Ledgard S.F. (2012). Water footprinting – A comparison of methods using New Zealand dairy farming as a case study. Agricultural Systems, 110, 30-40

 

The Risk of A Lifetime – Part Two – Unethical Balance

The following is the second part of the text about Rivka Weinberg’s book The Risk of a Lifetime, in which she explores How, When, and Why Procreation May Be Permissible.
If you haven’t read the first part, it is highly essential to do so before reading this one.

In any case, here is a quick recap. Procreation according Weinberg is not a gift, but it’s also not a predicament; it is a risk, a risk of a lifetime that people choose to impose on other people, and necessarily for their own benefit since being created can never be in the interests of a person before being created. And since this is the setting of creating a person, meaning, basically a selfish action that imposes a lifetime risk on another person, it needs to have a very good reason.

Weinberg suggests that procreation is a risk that can be justified by two principles she calls the ‘Principles of Procreative Permissibility’:

Motivation Restriction: Procreation must be motivated by the desire and intention to raise, love, and nurture one’s child once it is born.

Procreative Balance: Procreation is permissible only when the risk you impose as a procreator on your children would not be irrational for you to accept as a condition of your own birth (assuming that you will exist), in exchange for the permission to procreate under these risk conditions.

Weinberg uses a Kantian/Rawlsian framework for constructing these principles, explaining that the Kantian framework is suited to questions of procreative permissibility because it emphasizes the treatment of all persons as ends in themselves and stresses the importance of proper motivation. And the Rawlsian framework is particularly useful for questions of procreative permissibility because it is constructed to yield just principles in cases of distributive conflicts of interests and deliberated about under conditions constructed to reduce bias. She is aware that it is not common to think of procreation as a distributive conflict of interest, but argues that it is one:

“prospective parents have an interest in procreating whenever they please, and future children have an interest in excellent birth conditions. These interests are often in conflict. For example, if parents procreate while they are unemployed, their children will bear some of the costs of their parents’ procreative freedom. If we restrict procreative permissibility only to cases where the future children are likely to have extremely secure economic situations, people who cannot offer this to their children will bear the costs of the security of future children (a category that, in this case, will not include their own children).” (p.7)

In the previous part I have addressed her first principle, and in the following text I’ll address the second one.

Conflict of Interests?

Despite being absolutely aware of the fact that prospective parents may want to create children but their future children have no interest in being created, she addresses procreation as a conflict of interests regarding risk imposition.

“Risk imposers have an interest in doing the act that imposes a risk; those they place at risk have an interest in avoiding any harms resulting from the imposition of the risk. In the procreative case, parents have an interest in procreating, which imposes various risks on their children. To assess when the risk is permissible to impose, we consider the cost to the parents of restricting their risk-imposing activity and the costs children may bear if parental procreative risk imposition ripens into a harm. We are thus engaged in adjudicating a distributive conflict of interests.

Although parents and children have many interests in common, in fundamental ways, procreation involves a conflict of parent/child interests. Prospective parents have an interest in procreating; future people have an interest in optimal birth conditions. The procreative conflict consists in the conflict of interests between existing people with an interest in procreating and future people with an interest in optimal birth conditions.” (p. 155)

People may have an interest in optimal birth conditions when they are being created, but before being created no one has an interest in being created. There is no conflict of interests between prospective parents and their children before they are created. There is only people who are forcing their own interests on others when they are creating them. People have many interests regarding their own creation, but only once they have been created, not a moment before, and since the case in point regards ethical questions about creating people, not about treating existing people, there is no conflict of interests. A conflict of interests was relevant only had people had an interest in being created before it was forced on them. Presenting the issue as a genuine conflict of interests seems like an attempt to disguise the unavoidable coercion element, the intrinsically distinctive and unequal positions, as well as the fact that as explained in the first part it is unavoidably treating others as means to others’ ends.

Yet she suggests Contractualism to handle this seemingly conflict of interests:

 “Contractualism is designed to handle conflicts of interests, as it is fundamentally an account of how to interact with—how to make deals (contracts) with—others who are just as entitled to respect and autonomy as we are. How to balance what we want to pursue and how we wish to be treated with the rights and claims of others is a guiding point of all contractualist theories. The contractualist theory most directly aimed at adjudicating conflicts of interests is Rawlsian contractualism. That speaks in favor of it as a model for formulating our principles of procreative permissibility.” (p.157)

But you can’t sign a contract with someone who doesn’t exist. You can only impose a contract on someone who doesn’t exist and that’s exactly what happens in procreation. You can try to extract the most respectful, most carful contract you can possibly think of, but you can’t avoid it being coercive and it can never neutralize all the risks, which in the case of procreation, didn’t exist prior to the creation. As she herself admits, yet is ready to impose that risk anyway:

“No one can be absolutely sure that she will be able to fulfill her parental responsibilities since anyone can die anytime, or become incapacitated, homeless, and so on. So we will not set absolute standards of procreative care because that would impose too high a cost on parents. No one would be able to procreate if the ability to fulfill one’s parental responsibilities had to be absolutely guaranteed. But we won’t set very low standards either, for example, allowing impoverished, mentally ill adolescents to procreate, because that would impose too high a cost on the children.” (p. 62)

If she rejects the claim that the ability to fulfill one’s parental responsibilities has to be absolutely guaranteed because then no one would be able to procreate, it means that she wants to permit procreation and not that she had truly taken an ethical journey into the question of procreation. She rejects an absolutely valid conclusion because she finds it undesirable. That claim goes to show that her journey had an initial agenda. Why wouldn’t it be the case that no one should be able to procreate unless the ability to fulfill one’s parental responsibilities is absolutely guaranteed? It makes total sense. The fact that it’s also totally impossible doesn’t mean that we need to forsake this absolutely logical conclusion, but that we need to absolutely forsake procreation.
It looks like she is led by her desirable outcome, because when examining How, When, and Why Procreation May Be Permissible, the option that it may never be permissible can’t simply be ruled out. We mustn’t ignore such an important and self-evident condition as absolutely guaranteeing the ability to fulfill one’s parental responsibilities just because we don’t like what is inferred from that. What is the point of a philosophical inquiry if some conclusions are rejected simply because we don’t like them?

And of course, parents being unable to absolutely guarantee the fulfillment of their responsibilities, is only part of the risks imposed when creating people, there are many others, and she mentions some of them herself:

“Not only are there many ways for life to turn out really badly, there is also the matter of how wildly and incredibly uncertain life is. Adults who have been screened for all screenable genetic diseases may still give birth to a severely deformed, ill, disabled, suffering person; adults well placed to care for a child can drop dead anytime, lose their jobs, blow up their heretofore stable relationships; prosperous, productive societies can degenerate into civil war, anarchy, tyranny, and oppression; anyone can get what we might call a great start in life and come to a horrific end (and middle).” (p. 21)

But still argues that these risks can be justified as long as it fits the Procreative Balance Principle:

“Procreative Balance: Procreation is permissible when the risk you impose as a procreator on your children would not be irrational for you to accept as a condition of your own birth (assuming that you will exist), in exchange for the permission to procreate under these risk conditions.”

One of the fundamental problems involved in this principle is that people usually examine life according to their own lives and if when they are thinking about creating a new person their lives are fine in their view, then they falsely induce that life is fine in general. This observation is wrong not only because it is probably inaccurate and biased regarding their own lives, but also because it is wrong to make a personal life assessment when they are not even half way through (assuming that most people breed before their life is in its middle). But, of course, the worst thing about it is that people also tend to induce that since their life is fine then their children’s life will be fine too, and that is despite that they would be different people, who will live different lives. No one has any guarantee that their children’s lives would be even remotely similar to their own lives.

Furthermore, this procreative principle implies that existing people need to consider their own existence compared with non-existing people or with the option of their own non-existence, and both cases are impossible. A person can’t really remove oneself from its own existence and ignore its interest in continuing to exist (if one has such an interest), therefore, asking people to consider that the risk they are imposing on their own children would not be one that it is irrational for them to accept as a condition of their own birth, is for them, since they exist, like asking if they were willing to give up their own existence considering the risk involved with their creation. But that is obviously not the case and it is definitely not the case when it comes to creating new people. Had existing people never have existed they wouldn’t have to give up anything. And the same goes for people who don’t exist. Whom who never have existed don’t lose anything by not being created.
The person who is asked to reflect over its own creation while considering creating a new person exists and therefore probably balances its own existence with the option of never existing, and since the later seems to most people less desirable or even as a bad option, it seems that they are ready to take huge risks so not to “lose” their existence. That is despite that this is not what would have happened had they never existed. People are afraid of non-existence even though the issue is of them never existing in the first place, not stopping to exist. But people wrongfully imagine themselves giving up everything they have, even though it has no sense, since had they never existed they wouldn’t give up everything they have, nor would they experience giving up everything they have. And since they are making this fundamental mistake it seems rational to them to accept imposing risks, even huge ones, as a condition of their own birth and therefore also as a condition of the creation of their children.

So there is something inherently flawed about this principle as it makes people ask themselves the wrong question, while they actually need to be asking themselves a different one. Something like: I have experienced severe pain at least once during my lifetime, I was severely ill at least once during my lifetime, my heart was broken at least once during my lifetime, I have lost a loved one at least once during my lifetime, and I am working very hard all my life just to support myself; I don’t wish anyone to go through any of that, definitely not my own children. If I’ll create people they probably will experience all of this too, and if I don’t they won’t. They probably would also experience some great things but they will not be deprived of these things if I never create them. So I am actually causing my own children to experience severe pain at least once during their lifetime, severe illness at least once during their lifetime, broken-heartedness at least once during their lifetime, the loss of a loved one at least once during their lifetime, and to work very hard all of their lives, all for me to experience parenthood. What kind of a person wants to do that to others?

Insisting on such a procreative balance implies that not procreating must be a serious harm to people who want to. But isn’t it an indication of how lacking existence is? Of how basically lacking people are? Of how even adults are nonautonomous but are rather dependent and deficient for needing to create others, let alone infant others, to complete them? Had procreation been unforceful, unharmful and risk free, then it could have been permissible. But when the price is so high it is absolutely wrong. In order to fill people’s basically lacking existence they are creating more basically lacking people who will create more basically lacking people to fill their own basically lacking existence and so on. What’s the idea? that without creating new basically lacking people, existing basically lacking people will be harmed by their basically lacking existence so there is no choice but to create more and more basically lacking people?
This is another aspect of procreation being a sort of a Ponzi Scheme, one which I have referred to in the text Autobiographies, Biographies and Ponzi Schemes. And this cruel cycle of unnecessary and totally unbalanced imposition must be ended.

Unbalanced Sacrifice

Even if for the sake of the argument I’ll accept the claim that there’s truly a conflict of interests between people who want to create a person and the person they will create, and that sometimes the harm of not procreating is worth the risk of harm to the person being created, this is not the only implication of these principles. Given that miserable lives are being created all the time – and many of which regardless of the parents treating their children as autonomous people worthy of love and respect – what these principles are actually saying is that some’s misery is justified by the interests of others to procreate.

Weinberg prefers to frame the argument this way: procreation is sometimes ethically justified since many people have a strong interest in procreating and their interest is motivated by the desire and intention to raise, love, and nurture one’s child once it is born, and for most created people life is not at all bad. But the very same idea can be framed differently: procreation is sometimes ethically justified despite that it is always the case that for some created people, life would be miserable. The second formulation implies that procreation is justifying the imposition of miserable lives upon at least some created people, for the sake of people who want to procreate. But ethically we must prioritize the ones who would be imposed with something that they really wouldn’t want – life of misery had they existed, over the ones who would not get something they want, even if they really want it.

On a global level procreation is not a gamble, it is not a risk, because it is absolutely certain that some persons would be forced to live extremely miserable lives. The question is who. Since people tend to feel that bad things only happen to other people, they dismiss the option of misery happening to their children. And even if for the sake of the argument I’ll accept that the chances of each couple to create a person whose life is extremely miserable are low, this is not the case on a global scale. Meaning, somewhere in the world, miserable persons will be created. And that fact turns the argument from a risk that some of the people would have horrible lives, to a decision that some of the people would have horrible lives if procreation is permissible, because cases of misery are certain, and there are no cases of procreation in which there is a certainty of no misery. So people who decide to procreate are not only taking a risk on someone else’s suffering, they also approve and strengthen the claim that the suffering of some is justified because of the interests of others – people who want to procreate. The immorality of these principles stems not only from the decision to take risks on someone else’s life, but also from the decision that some would be sacrificed so that others could have what they want.

Individuals are sacrificed for others’ desires. That is since even if individuals are being created by people who are motivated by the desire and intention to raise, love, and nurture one’s child once it is born, some would still be miserable. And so, on a global scale, procreation is sacrificing individuals for others’ desires.
Once there is an option for creating a miserable life, procreation is ethically undefendable. The way it is nevertheless being defended is actually by a sort of tyranny of the (existing) majority.

One might suggest that what we ought to do is weigh the interests of the people who want to procreate against the suffering of the ones who would lead miserable lives, but that is a false equivalency. Especially since procreation is not only forcing needless and pointless suffering on the created person, but is also, and in fact first and foremost, forcing needless and pointless suffering on thousands of other sentient creatures, since each person created is harming thousands of sentient creatures during a lifetime.

It is very hard to accurately assess the harms caused by each person since it depends on various factors such as location, socioeconomic status, consumption habits, life expectancy, livelihood, diet and etc., however, regardless of any circumstances, harming numerous others is inevitable.
And the most immediate and prominent harm is caused by what people eat.
Every person has to eat, and every food has a price. Unfortunately, most people are choosing the ones with the highest price – animal based foods.
Since most humans, more than 95% of them actually, are not even vegans – the most basic and primal ethical decision one must make – procreation is practically accepting the murder of thousands of creatures.
And all this is the harms involved with direct consumption of animal based food and clothing. Each human harms many more animals in plenty of other ways by consuming various other products, including vegan ones, and by participating in various other activities. Everything has a price, nothing comes for free, everything is somehow harmful to someone.

Procreation is not only creating a subject of harms, but also a small unit of exploitation and pollution. Therefore, the question is not is it justified that people would impose a risk of a lifetime on another person so they can fulfil their desire to procreate, but is it justified that people would impose immense harm on many others so that they would fulfil their desire to procreate.
The question in point is not is it ethical to take the risk of creating miserable lives, but is it ethical to impose miserable lives on many others so that a truly tiny minority would experience parenthood. How can it be acceptable to force lives full of suffering on thousands of sentient creatures, just so that one unethical preference of would-be parents won’t be frustrated?

But it goes even further than that. What should be weighed against the interests of people who want to procreate is not only the people who would be born into miserable lives, and not only the animals who would be harmed by the newborns of the current people who want to procreate, but all the harms, and all the misery, and all the suffering that would ever be caused by humans. So the true balancing is even crueler considering that the harm to whom who will not get what they want, can be summed up with one generation only, compared with harm to infinite number of generations, theoretically until the sun burns. Eventually we are talking about sacrificing the interests of only the people who currently exist and want to procreate, and only for the “right” reasons, and only if they meet the criterion of the procreative balance. How can the deprivation of one desire, of only a part of only one generation, be seriously compared with the continuance and systematical deprivation of whomever would exist if that part of that one generation will procreate?

Wasn’t it worth it to sacrifice people’s desire to procreate 150 years ago was it possible, so to prevent the horrors of Auschwitz? Is the harm of preventing something desirable from someone, greater than the harms of the Second World War? Wasn’t it worth it to prevent all the people who lived 150 years ago from expressing their desire to procreate so all the horrors of the 20th century could be avoided, not to mention all the horrors that occurred since then and will occur in the future?

Sentient creatures who would exist in the future are not less important than sentient creatures who live right now. And sentient creatures who would live in the future infinitely outnumber the ones who are alive today, let alone merely the humans who want to procreate and meet the criterion of the principles of procreative permissibility. So giving these people the same moral weight as all the creatures that would ever be forced to suffer is a serious case of myopia, speciesism and cruelty.

One needs to be extremely speciesist to ignore that there is more than one species, and be extremely biased to ignore that there is more than one timeframe. The harm to people from the present is extremely marginal compared with the harm to other species and to people who will exist in the future.

Once realizing that procreation is not good in itself but is only good for the ones who want it, and that it has a tremendous price, clearly it is better to prevent it as soon as possible, as stopping it will hurt only some of the existing people, and not stopping it will endlessly harm more and more sentient creatures. The harm to part of the existing people, by preventing them from procreating, can’t even come close to seriously countervail the harms to generations upon generations of sentient creatures.

Objecting to harm the current generation by preventing it from procreating is forcing endless harms on an endless number of individuals.

And since people don’t even take seriously the possibility that their own children might suffer extremely, there is no chance they would ever take seriously the certainty that numerous generations of sentient creatures would suffer extremely because of their procreation. That’s why we mustn’t wait until people would understand that it is ethically impossible to justify procreation, but do everything we can to make it impossible to procreate.

References

Rawls, John. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge, MA Harvard University Press 2001)

Weinberg, Rivka. Existence: who needs it? The non-identity problem and merely possible people
2012 Bioethics ISSN 0269-9702

Weinberg Rivka The Moral Complexity Of Sperm Donation
Bioethics ISSN 0269-9702 (print); 1467-8519 (online) doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.2007.00624.x
Volume 22 Number 3 2008 pp 166–178

Weinberg Rivka. The Risk Of A Lifetime (Oxford University Press, 2006)

The Risk of A Lifetime – Part One – Unethical Motivation

In her book The Risk of a Lifetime Rivka Weinberg explores How, When, and Why Procreation May Be Permissible.
As the headline implies she thinks that procreation is a risk of a lifetime, and as the subheading suggests, it is a permissible risk but under certain conditions.
Since the road she takes to explain How, When, and Why Procreation May Be Permissible goes through various issues which I have already addressed in previous texts, such as her Hazmat Theory Of Parental Responsibility, the Non-Identity Problem, David Benatar’s Quality Of Life Argument, Seana Shiffrin’s consent argument, and Rawls theory of justice, here I’ll focus on the core of her book – the ‘Principles of Procreative Permissibility’.
For a more complete critical observation of the rest of the ideas she addresses in the book, please read the texts I have just referred to.

The Principles of Procreative Permissibility

Despite that the very first sentence of the book is: “Everybody is somebody’s fault” and despite that shortly after she writes:

“It’s mind-blowing, really. Here we are, in our strange and vast universe, living with many unknowns, uncertainties, and difficulties, and what do we do? We decide to create a creature like ourselves, a sentient, conscious person, with full moral status and a future largely unknown except for the fact that the person will be helpless and dependent for a very long time. How odd of us. Who do we think we are, anyway? Where do we get off? When we procreate, what are we doing and why are we doing it? (p. 15)

Her book is not at all an antinatalist one and she doesn’t think life is a predicament. But she also undauntedly rejects the common notion that life is a gift. As opposed to gifts, which are given for free, can be enjoyed or ignored, but very unlikely to harm the recipient, Weinberg argues that life is not free, it can’t be ignored, and it can definitely harm the created. One has to work hard to enjoy life, and if one ignores life, one is likely to suffer, and of course for many created people life is extremely harmful. So life, even when considered good, is not a gift.
But more importantly, life according to her is not a gift, nor a benefit bestowed by parents on their children, because no one needed, wanted or had an interest in being created before it happened, and no one existed in any other form before being created so no one can be benefited by being created. In her own words: “the future person does not have a good or any state at all to improve, benefit, or better until after the procreative act is complete” (p. 20)
She agrees that procreation is not and can’t at all be an action for the sake of the created people, but is an action for the sake of the parents, as the children are not subjects of interests before they are being created, so how can their creation be for their own sake?

So procreation according Weinberg is not a gift, but it’s also not a predicament, it is a risk, a risk of a lifetime that people choose to impose on other people, and necessarily for their own benefit since being created is never in the interests of a person before it exists. And since this is the setting of creating a person, according to her, meaning, basically a selfish action that imposes a lifetime risk on another person, it needs to have a very good reason.

Weinberg suggests that procreation is a risk that can be justified by two principles she calls the ‘Principles of Procreative Permissibility’:

Motivation Restriction: Procreation must be motivated by the desire and intention to raise, love, and nurture one’s child once it is born.

Procreative Balance: Procreation is permissible only when the risk you impose as a procreator on your children would not be irrational for you to accept as a condition of your own birth (assuming that you will exist), in exchange for the permission to procreate under these risk conditions.

Weinberg uses a Kantian/Rawlsian framework for constructing these principles, explaining that the Kantian framework is suited to questions of procreative permissibility because it emphasizes the treatment of all persons as ends in themselves and stresses the importance of proper motivation. And the Rawlsian framework is particularly useful for questions of procreative permissibility because it is constructed to yield just principles in cases of distributive conflicts of interests and deliberated about under conditions constructed to reduce bias. She is aware that it is not common to think of procreation as a distributive conflict of interest, but argues that it is one:

“prospective parents have an interest in procreating whenever they please, and future children have an interest in excellent birth conditions. These interests are often in conflict. For example, if parents procreate while they are unemployed, their children will bear some of the costs of their parents’ procreative freedom. If we restrict procreative permissibility only to cases where the future children are likely to have extremely secure economic situations, people who cannot offer this to their children will bear the costs of the security of future children (a category that, in this case, will not include their own children).” (p.7)

In the following text I’ll address her first principle, and in the second part I’ll address the second one.

An End To Others Being Means

With heavy reliance on a Kantian ethical framework Weinberg considers the motivation behind procreation and the treatment of all persons as ends in themselves, to be extremely crucial:

“Just as Kantian contractualism emphasizes the importance of being properly motivated, we have determined that proper procreative motivation is crucial to its permissibility. Proper procreative motivation is important because it helps to ensure that we are procreating in ways that are not disrespectful to children or inconsistent with our broadly liberal values of autonomy, respect, and equality. For example, procreating because one wants to engage in the parent-child relationship as a nurturing parent would be an acceptable procreative motive, but procreating to impress the neighbors would be a problematic procreative motive, regardless of outcome, because it does not treat the future child as a person deserving of respect and value in her own right.” (p. 154)

However, there seems to be a basic and fundamental oxymoron with forcing existence on other people and treating them as ends in themselves. While we should, and hopefully can, treat existing others as ends in themselves, creating others without them desiring, needing, wanting, or having any interests in being created, can’t be treating them as ends in themselves, as they didn’t exist before their existence was forced on them. Weinberg totally rejects people’s false statement that they are creating other people to benefit these people, so how is it that it is impossible and logically implausible to create someone for its own benefit but not that it is impossible and logically implausible to create someone as an end in itself?

The fact that these ends are to raise, love, and nurture their child once it is born, doesn’t make them means to the child’s end, or the child to be an end in itself. The desire and intention to raise, love, and nurture one’s child once it is born, is still the parents’ desire and never the child’s, since before being created there is no child to have any desire.
Treating a child as an end in itself once it is born doesn’t retroactively make the creation of that child an end in itself. The child was still necessarily born for others’ ends.

In order for a person’s creation to truly be for its own end, it is insufficient for the parents to treat their child as an end in itself, nor for that person to find an end of its own to its own existence, but that the answer to the question ‘why was I created?’ be ‘since I had an end X’. Clearly there is no such option since no one has its own ends before existing. The answer is always ‘since my parents had an end X’. A person can absolutely say ‘now that I exist I have an end X’ and it can absolutely be a reason for its existence after being created, but it can’t be a reason for its creation. No matter how many ends a person would find along its existence, the end of its creation will always be its parents’.

Therefore I find it hard to see how procreation can be defended using a Kantian framework since people are never created as ends in themselves but always as means to their parents’ ends. Being created is never needed or desired by the person being created. It is forced on each and every person, always, and necessarily for motives of others. Or if to go back to the first sentence of the book – “Everybody is somebody’s fault”…

The case in point is about creating people, not about how to treat people after creating them was already decided.
It seems that as far as Weinberg goes the instrumentalization bound with creating people can be covered up if their parents intend to treat them as separate and valuable persons in their own right after they were created. Obviously, treating a person as worthy of respect of its own after being created is highly crucial, however it shouldn’t retroactively change the instrumental circumstances of its creation. It is impossible to create someone not as a mean to others’ ends. And no matter how that person would be treated after being created, nothing can retroactively change that fact.

Weinberg mentions along the book some awful motives for procreation, probably as a rhetoric exercise, hoping to put a positive spin on the motivation she claims can make it permissible. But arguing that – creating a person if there is no intention or ability to ensure that the child would feel self-respect, that she is entitled to love and consideration in her own right – is wrong, doesn’t make the opposite right. They both can be wrong, despite one of them being much worse than the other.
I agree that it will be hard for a child to develop basic self-respect if s/he is not treated as worthy of respect, but that is a good reason to treat people as worthy of respect, and not at all a reason to create people in the first place. Furthermore, the risk imposition, the selfishness, the paternalism, the pointlessness, the pain, the frustration, the stress, the boredom, the sickness, the death and the fear of death, are all still there. All that mentioning some horrible reasons to create a person can prove is that there are certainly even worse reasons to create a person than the ones she suggests, but it can’t prove that her reasons are permissible.

If I want to do something that involves someone else, let alone when that person has no interest in that something happening before it does, I must make sure that at least that person will not be harmed by my desirable action. There is no such option when people are creating people. In fact, it is the opposite, we can be sure that all created people will be harmed, and no motivation and intention to raise, love, and nurture them can ensure that they won’t.

In addition, good intentions do not guarantee good performances (wanting to be a respectful and loving parent does not guarantee succeeding in being one), even allegedly succeeding in treating people as separate persons in their own right, and as entitled to respect and being valued for their own sake, doesn’t ensure good outcomes. Awful and unrespectful relationships between parents and children don’t have exclusivity in misery. There are plenty of other causes and reasons for misery, and there are many miserable children of parents who sincerely tried to be as respectful and as loving as possible. It is simply not at all a guaranteed recipe as life throws plenty of shit at people, and parents are absolutely helpless in protecting their children from all of it.

Wrong Motivation

Besides being irrelevant and insufficient when it comes to questions of creating new people, and besides being selfish and instrumental as well, the mere desire for a relationship which is highly, inevitably, and prolongedly – unequal, paternalistic and controlling – is highly questionable.

Doesn’t the fact that most people don’t want to adopt but desire a biological child of their own, arouse suspicion that it might not be merely the desire to raise, love, and nurture a child? Isn’t it obvious that there is another motive here which involves hubris or narcissism, as people seem to insist on seeing their own genes being spread, on creating an extension of themselves, a mini-me, or something of this sort?
And shouldn’t the fact that the few who are willing to adopt, disproportionally prefer a baby and not a grown child (despite knowing that most of the other people who are willing to adopt prefer to adopt a baby as well, so if they will insist on adopting a baby, parentless grown children might never be adopted), set alarm bells ringing regarding people’s real motives as clearly they prefer that the person they supposedly want to raise, love, and nurture would be as little, as dependent and as cute as possible? Isn’t it because the younger and the more dependent their child is the easier the imprinting process would be? Doesn’t it at all involve ensuring that their child would be more likely to love them back and to fill them with a feeling of power and competent (as after all they are supposedly able to take care of all of someone else’s needs, a feeling that is not available for them with bigger and more independent children)? Doesn’t that preference have something to do with them wanting a cute gadget to love, all the more so one that is way more likely to be an extension of themselves than a grown child is expected to be?
Would people create new people if they were born independent, speaking, intellectually equal adults? No way. And that means that at least part of what they desire is an unequal, paternalistic and controlling relationship.
And of course this case is not even of participating in such a relationship but of creating one, all the more so exactly because that’s what it is (again, people would not create independent, speaking, intellectually equal adults).

So even if that was truly the motivation of parents, there is something awfully wrong about it. And unfortunately, usually, the motivation is even worse than the one Weinberg refers to.
I fail to comprehend how a desire and intention to raise, love, and nurture one’s child once it is born can justify the blunt and unambiguous elements of imposition, selfishness, and instrumentalization, bound with its creation. Elements which Weinberg is well aware of:

“even if the child’s life is good for the child once the child exists, it is still not a benefit to the child to have been procreated. That’s why we cannot easily claim to create a child to further the child’s interests. The child has interests only if the child exists; otherwise we have no real subject for interests at all. Therefore we do not further the child’s interests by bringing it into existence. We must face the fact that we don’t procreate for the sake of our children. We procreate because we want to. Hopefully, we want to because we want to engage in the parent-child relationship as a parent and participate in a family. Thus we come to an understanding of how we may procreate with a justifiable motive. The parental motive seems justifiable because acting on it may satisfy a unique and legitimate interest of existing people and, arguably, may do so in a way that can be respectful of the future child before the child is conceived and beneficial to the child once the child exists.” (p. 39)

If humans have such a strong motivation to express their desire to love and take care of others, why not directing it towards whom who are in real need instead of creating new unnecessary needy people? By that they are adding insult to injury, since they are devoting most of their time, energy and resources to needs that they have unnecessarily created, instead of to the various needs that were already there. So in that sense, creating new people is not only disrespectful towards the created people, as they are created to serve as mediums for the expression of their creators’ desire to love and take care of others, but it is also disrespectful towards existing people in need who are treated as if their need is less important than a created unnecessary need.
And it all comes with a very high price, imposing unnecessary lifetime risks on others, treating children as means to others’ ends, forsaking people in real need, and creating additional and unnecessary units of suffering, exploitation and pollution.

It is hard to call something a truly and authentically loving relationship when one side is totally depended on the other. The child being absolutely needy and helpless, develops attachment to its parents because they provide vital first aid, mainly through feed and a sense of protection. And that positive association is being formed regardless of any intrinsic quality of the parents. It is not a choice or a preference, but more like a conditioned reflex. This is more like a fixed attachment, an imprinting, than anything authentic.
It is such an unequal, paternalistic and commanding relationship that it needs to be condemned not perpetuated and justified. The fact that it is very common, natural and universal doesn’t make it right.
A structurally unequal and dominating relationship is not justified because these features are natural and inevitable. In fact, since this relationship is naturally and inevitably structurally unequal and dominating, creating it must be avoided.

Procreation involves a dubious motivation and it is wrong to describe it as if it can be a product of a pure desire to raise, love and nurture another person. It is mainly a biological impulse, that can be controlled, is unnecessary, and necessarily has tremendous prices.

Creating a person is creating a biological gadget, even if its creators don’t treat it as one. It is a biological gadget that is supposed to provide its creators love and satisfaction, a sense of power and competence, a purpose for their existence, to ease their existence’s pointlessness, to ease their boredom, to give them a reason to do staff, to recover and maintain their relationship, normalize them in the eyes of society and etc. These motives are rarely openly stated but they are some of the real reasons behind procreation and often behind the motivation to raise, love and nurture one’s child once it is born.

Disrespectful Unequal and Nonautonomous

Having a so called proper motive may be important to ensure that the parents are not disrespectful to their children or inconsistent with broadly liberal values of autonomy, respect, and equality, after the person was created, but it can’t retroactively change the fact that that person was created for its parents’ ends, without equally respecting that person’s autonomy. These values are some of the crucial factors for insuring a respectful treatment of an existing person, but practically they are hardly relevant even for existing children, as they are not really treated as equally respectful autonomous people, and they are not even theoretically relevant for non-existing people.

Unilaterally forcing someone into a relationship which that person can’t really get out of isn’t being respectful of that person. Once existing, a person can’t undo its own existence, undo or change the genetic makeup forced on that person, undo or change the environmental conditions forced on that person, or undo or change the relationships forced on that person.
And there is not even a clean, safe and respectful exit option from any of that, so how is it respectful of the person created?

Suicide, which is not by all means undoing existence, as explained in the text about suicide, is a horrible, harmful, scary and dangerous option. Disconnection from the forced relationship is only optional from a certain age and even then it is always complicated as people are not psychologically built to disassociate from their family, it always comes with a price, and even if it didn’t, it can’t retroactively cancel out the crucial and irreversible effects a family has on a person. Weinberg may wonder why would anyone even want to have these options if its parents really loved and nurtured that person? And maybe most wouldn’t, but some might, and anyway the point is not statistical but fundamental, forcing someone into a situation with no exit options is trapping, not respecting. If there is no respectful exit, how can there be a respectful entrance?

It sure sounds highly disrespectful to create someone to impress the neighbors (one of Weinberg’s examples, which was earlier mentioned), but is it really fundamentally different, in the instrumentalization sense, than the case of procreating because one wants to engage in a parent-child relationship as a nurturing parent? I am not saying it is the same, or that it is equally bad, it is not, but I am wondering how is creating someone as a love and nurture gadget for its parents, so fundamentally and even categorically different than many other selfish motives?
I understand that that person may feel more respected if its parents say that they wanted to raise, love, and nurture a child and not that they wanted to impress the neighbors if are asked why did they create him/her. However, if that person thinks a little bit more deeply about it, the parents wanted to raise, love, and nurture a child, they didn’t want to raise, love, and nurture him/her specifically, and it is them who wanted to raise, love, and nurture a child, not him/her specifically who wanted to be raised, loved and nurtured. So I understand why it feels more respectful than most other reasons, yet I fail to understand why this motive is categorically different.

Impressing the neighbors sounds awfully selfish and instrumental, but a desire and intention to raise, love, and nurture one’s child once it is born is also selfish and instrumental as in both cases it is not the created person’s need or desire but its parents’. In both cases a person was created unilaterally and according to the parents’ will. The fact that the created person didn’t have a will to consider before being created doesn’t mean that it was nevertheless respected because it will be respected after that person is created. The respect in case should be regarding its creation not its nurture. Respecting someone’s will in existence doesn’t retroactively respect someone’s will in being created, and since there is no will to be created, creating a person can’t be respectful but only forceful.

The desire for a relationship which in its essence is highly unequal and paternalistic, is wrong, and as opposed to her claim it is disrespectful to children and inconsistent with broadly liberal values such as equality, respect and autonomy. Weinberg argues that there are many cases of paternalism that we find justified, but that doesn’t mean that paternalism is unproblematic, only that it is sometimes necessary. It is still a problem and when it is justified it is probably because it is the lesser of two evils. It is justified since without it, someone is going to be harmed. Paternalism towards existing people who lost their ability for autonomy isn’t like creating people who have no ability for autonomy. The fact that we are bound to accept that there are some cases that paternalism is necessary isn’t by any means a justification to create more of it. We need to try and prevent paternalism as much as we can, not justify the creation of more and more of it because sometimes it is necessary. And it is never necessary to create an unnecessary situation which is known to be inherently and inevitably paternalistic.

Some argue that this paternalism is only temporary, but it is for a very long time, it is not at all necessary, and it is not a case of the lesser of two evils for these people. As opposed to the case of paternalism towards existing people, in the case of procreation the choice is not paternalism or harm, as no one is harmed by not being created.

And I disagree that the paternalism is temporary, since by the time the created people become supposedly autonomic they are already deeply designed by their genetic makeup, their surroundings, their so far life experiences (mainly earlier formative experiences), and of course by their parents who usually conduct it all. So how autonomic can a person exactly be when almost everything about that person was predesigned by various crucial factors that determine who that person is and who that person can be, from many aspects. People choose practically nothing of almost each and every crucial factor that has made them who they are, so how can they ever be who they really are? How can they really be autonomous?

There are various elements of coercion in parents-children relationships, there is no option for children to choose until a relatively late stage in their life, and even then these choices are made out of a very particular position which wasn’t chosen by them. The fact that people can’t choose, shape or even influence their own existence conditions including their genetics, their environment, their family, and their early formative experiences makes their creation even more wrong, disrespectful, and inconsistent with broadly liberal values of autonomy, respect, and equality.

Someone’s existence is always a result of an action that doesn’t respect the created person’s independence as a person because consent is never given by that person, the person never chooses anything about its own existence, including the very fact of having one, the person doesn’t have a safe and harmless way of ending its own existence, the person can’t choose its parents, the rest of the family, its neighborhood, its society and etc.
These things are always being selected for everyone. The most affected person never gets to choose anything, and that is always wrong and disrespectful.

Most of the critical things are determined for a person before it becomes an autonomous entity, therefore s/he never really is one in a deeper sense. And that is under the more liberal view, the more inclined you are towards nature in the famous nature vs. nurture debate, the less relevant the autonomy option is. However since no one really chooses one’s environment, it doesn’t really matter whether it is more nature or more nurture, as it is definitely not autonomy. No one really has autonomy over one’s life. No one really freely chooses its own projects, goals, meaning or even its own character.

This is inherent to human life and it is unavoidable. Of course there can be differences, clearly people raised by parents who highly emphasis their autonomy and choice are more likely to become more independent compared with people who were raised by controlling and strict parents. However no parents can avoid controlling their children and highly affecting their autonomy. They are deciding everything for their children, particularly at early ages. They decide for them where they live, they often unilaterally change where they live, they decide what they will wear, what they will eat, what they do, what they don’t do, who to be with, who not to be with and etc. And if parents really want to create autonomous people they must constantly and impartially expose them to an immense variety of options, which is obviously totally unrealistic, and it would only partially deal with only part of the problem which is the environmental effects. It won’t deal with many other environmental effects that parents have absolutely no control over, and it won’t deal with the genetic makeup that no one has chosen but everyone must endure.

Every aspect of children’s lives is controlled by their parents, but what I am mostly bothered with here is not the structured and inherent paternalism but that in many senses people are significantly designed by their parents, and by many other factors which they have not chosen or can retroactively affect. The more profound aspect of non-autonomy is that people don’t get to choose who they are, who they will be, who they can be, who they want to be, their boundaries and etc. This is not a temporary coercion but a lifetime one.

Procreation is creating a person. A person that not only has not chosen to be created, but also has not chosen anything involved with its creation nor most of the most crucial elements in determining who that person is. Procreation is creating a person who is forced to be the carrier of certain genetic makeup, environment, and formative experiences, without any option to really evade their crucial effect, an effect that in one way or another will be part of every choice that person would ever make. Way more than totally controlling their lives until a certain age (as important as it is in itself), that is the profound coercion and non-autonomy that is intrinsically involved in creating a person.

In conclusion, I disagree with Weinberg that this motivation ensures that people are procreating in ways that are respectful to children or consistent with broadly liberal values of autonomy, respect, and equality, or that this motivation is categorically different in the sense of treating children as means to others’ ends. I think that this motivation is nevertheless disrespectful, unequal, non-autonomous, and instrumental.
But even if I agreed with Weinberg, and even if such a motivation could have been genuine (and not extremely problematic, to say the least, and not disrespectful to children, and not inconsistent with broadly liberal values of autonomy, respect, and equality), what does it say about procreation if one of the two principles of procreative permissibility is what should have been the most self-evident reason for procreating? It is awfully sad that people need to be told that they must be motivated by the desire and intention to raise, love, and nurture one’s child once it is born, and not by any other motivation, when they are planning to create a person.
The fact that she seriously argues that such a motivation must be initial to procreation only strengthens antinatalism as it is supposed to be extremely clear. And the fact that not only is it rarely the motivation, but that usually there is not even a feeling or need to come up with explicit motivations for procreation, or any thought about such a profound and crucial decision whatsoever, makes antinatalism even stronger. It indicates on the ease with which people are imposing risks of a lifetime on other people. And that disrespectful ease means that people are far from being responsible enough in order to put the fate of others in their hands.
If humanity has reached the 21st century and it needs a philosopher to dedicate a whole book to explain people under which circumstances procreation may be permissible, and these would be that they are motivated by the desire and intention to raise, love, and nurture one’s child once it is born, then clearly procreation mustn’t be permissible under any circumstances.
If it needs to be explained methodically and while eliminating unjustified and false motives it means that procreation mostly happens for unjustified and false motives. And if it mostly happens for unjustified and false motives there is a problem with the agents, since it is not that the “justified” and “right” motives are complicated, but rather that they should have been absolutely self-evident. But they are absolutely not. And that is extremely worrying.
If such an obvious factor must not only be mentioned but is one of the two formulated principles, then obviously there is something terribly wrong with the reasons people procreate and have been procreating so far. And if something is so wrong with the reasons people procreate and have been procreating so far, then maybe she doesn’t need to make the effort and formulate principles that can justify it, but conclude that people better never to have breed.

The second part of this text addresses Weinberg’s second principle of procreative permissibility: Procreative Balance

References

Benatar David. Better Never to Have Been (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006)

Shiffrin, S.V. Wrongful life, procreative responsibility, and the significance of harm. 1999
Legal Theory 5: 117–148

Weinberg, Rivka. Existence: who needs it? The non-identity problem and merely possible people
2012 Bioethics ISSN 0269-9702

Weinberg Rivka The Moral Complexity Of Sperm Donation

Bioethics ISSN 0269-9702 (print); 1467-8519 (online) doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.2007.00624.x

Volume 22 Number 3 2008 pp 166–178

Weinberg Rivka. The Risk Of A Lifetime (Oxford University Press, 2006)

 

Imposing Imposition

The leitmotif of antinatalism must be, in my view, the harm to others. As broadly claimed in many former texts, especially in Harm to Others, the worst aspect of procreation is not the harm caused to the created people but the harm caused by the created people. When considering each and every effect a person has on others, then the thousands if not tens of thousands of victims of each created person are the main victims of procreation and therefore must be the main claim against procreation.

Having said that, obviously the fact that the harm to others should be the central ethical reason never to procreate, doesn’t by any means diminish the severity, cruelty, and criminalness of creating people regardless of their harm to others. Evidently, many of the texts in this blog solely focus on the harm to the created people. Furthermore, obviously, the two perspectives are not at all in contradiction or clash, and in fact they may intertwine, and that is the point I wish to make in this text.

Life in this world is inherently violent, forceful, coercive and exploitive. From the moment people are born, they are bound to cause harm to others. Existing without harming others is not an option. Everything that was ever made is at the expense of someone, in some way. In many cases, numerous someones in various ways. Nothing is produced out of nothing, and nothing has no impact at all. Everything people do affects others. And it starts even before people are born as many of the antepartum procedures involve harm to others, exemplified mainly in the production, testing and waste of medical equipment.
But obviously that is only the beginning of a lifelong harmful impact on others that all people necessarily cause. A harmful impact that is caused by everyone, every day, through every action. From the houses they live in, their workplaces, the roads from their houses to their workplaces, the vehicles they are using on these roads, their furniture, their electrical appliances, their use of electricity, their clothes, the soaps they are using to clean their clothes, their toys, their shoes, their cosmetics, their beloved mobile phones, their use of anything made out of steel, copper, mercury, silver, gold, rubber, wood and most definitely plastic, their use of anything that causes some amount of pollution including CO2 (practically everything), and of course every piece of food they consume. That includes plant based food as well since every plant based food item is in one way or another a product of dispossessing, plundering, habitat destructing, poisoning, trampling, starving, dehydrating, air polluting, water polluting, climate alteration, land alteration, water waste, oil drilling, and etc. However, as long as 95% of people consume animal products, procreation is first and foremost a perpetuation of the most extreme torture system ever in history.

When creating people, parents are not only putting their children in harm’s way, they are forcing their children to put other sentient creatures in a highway of harm. They are forcing their children to force others to feel pain, fear, despair, diseases, boredom, loneliness, hunger, thirst, exhaustion, frustration, loss, crowdedness, suffocation, burns, bruises, mutilations, freezing, boiling, enslavement, slaughter and every other horrible thing people are doing to other animals and other people.

Life is necessarily an imposition not only in the sense that each necessarily starts with an imposition, but also because each is necessarily sustained by imposition. So parents are not only imposing existence on their children, they are also imposing on their children further imposition – the imposition on others to be exploited, polluted, and sacrificed for these children’s sustainability in the least worse case, and merely for these children’s trivial pleasures in the worst case.

The parents are, in effect, corrupting their own children. This is unjust toward the children who are imposed to be units of suffering, exploitation and pollution. The fact that there is no alternative to existing while imposing suffering, exploitation and pollution, is not a justification for this imposition, let alone for imposing this imposition.

Most parents are absolutely ignorant of the real scope of the harm their children would cause, but nowadays, many are at least aware of terms such as carbon footprint, ecological burden and overpopulation, and they all know that meat comes from animals who didn’t choose to live in factory farms and didn’t kill themselves. So when they are creating new people they know that not only that their own children would necessarily be harmed, but also that they will necessarily harm others, and so they are imposing their children with being wrongdoers from birth. No one chooses neither to be born, nor to be born a unit of suffering, exploitation and pollution. That is imposed on everyone as part of the imposition of their existence. People don’t become suffering, exploitation and pollution units as a result of their own choices, they are all born ones. Most will later choose to be huge units of suffering, exploitation and pollution instead of the smallest possible, but that’s another argument. The point here is that being a wrongdoer is inevitable and it was imposed on every person created, and that is another reason why no one should ever procreate.

Procreation is creating people who can’t be unharmful even if they wanted to.
Most wouldn’t care about harming others, but the ones who would are imposed to live with constant guilt and shame, with angst and rage, and maybe even depression, despair and self-hatred. It is quite tragic that the more caring and compassionate people are, the greater was the sin of creating them, as they are the ones (compared to other created people of course) who are most affected by the imposition of their imposition.

Some vegans for example are furious with their parents for forcing them to consume animals before they had an option to choose otherwise. It is extremely frustrating for them to realize that others were forced to suffer so extremely for their sake. They were forced to be exploiters of others without their consent, their awareness or any ability to comprehend the kind of torture they were forced to participate in, and up until a certain point with no ability to choose otherwise, or at least reduce their share and act so others would reduce their share in the global hell which is existence.
They are in no way the main victims, the main victims are obviously their victims, but at least to the more caring, compassionate and moral people, the thought that their existence is bound with the harm to others is very harming in itself.

The fact that all people, even the few who really care about others and really don’t want to harm anyone, have no choice but to hurt others, is another reason not to procreate since at least in the case of caring and sensitive people, that is part of their victimization. And that terrible situation can be avoided by avoiding procreation. If no one is created, no one could harm anyone.

But of course it is much more profound than the victimization of people of this kind. The fact that even theoretically it is impossible to fulfil the most basic ethical requirement – do no harm, indicates how structurally and inherently corrupted and unethical existence is.
In another text I argued that it is extremely unfair to force someone into a structurally and inherently unjust world, and here, more or less on the same token, I argue that it is extremely unethical to force someone into a world where that someone cannot be ethical.

Parents are condemning their children to be unethical from the beginning of their existence.

People who are aware of this necessary feature of existence and nevertheless choose to procreate are engaging in evil crimes and are forcing their children to do so as well.

The ethical reaction to this fact must be to refrain from procreation.
Only that people are not ethical creatures, therefore they don’t really care that their children would also be unethical creatures, who in their turn won’t care that their children are unethical creatures and so on and so forth, until someday, someone would somehow find a way to stop this endless circle of misery. Would it be you?

History of Antinatalism – As Impressive as Depressive

According to the book History of Antinatalism – How Philosophy Has Challenged the Question of Procreation, philosophy has started to challenge the question of procreation more or less since philosophy has started to challenge any question. The first mentioned and quoted philosophers in the book are the first philosophers mentioned and quoted in any book, meaning the pre-Socratics, including whom who is considered to be the first philosopher in history – Thales of Miletus who was born according to estimation between 624 to 620 BC, as well as Heraclitus (540-470 BC), Parmenides (515-450), and Anaxagoras (500-428 BC), and ancient Greek playwrights such as Sophocles (495-406 BC) and Euripides (480-406 BC). The book’s editor considers Thales to be not only the first philosopher to challenge the question of procreation but to be the first antinatalist, since when he was asked why he is childless, he replied ‘because I so love the children’.
The book is full of examples such as this, as well as many indirect but significant contributions to challenging the question of procreation, from several philosophers, in the course of almost 3,000 years. From the mentioned Thales, to Aristotle to whom an entire chapter is devoted, to Blaise Pascal, Leibniz, Montesquieu (“we should bewail people when being born and not after their death“), Schopenhauer obviously, Kierkegaard, Jean-Paul Sartre, to explicit and unmistakable antinatalist philosophers such as Peter Wessel Zapffe and Emil Cioran, and until present day antinatalist philosophers.

However, as impressive as this detailing of the history of Antinatalism is, the fact that the philosophical challenges of the question of procreation are ancient, and were made by various thinkers, from various thought traditions, including plenty of religious ones, is actually very depressing since it means that many people, from various different cultures and thought traditions, including religious ones, had plenty of time to seriously challenge procreation, yet they haven’t.

I find the book very frustrating not because its content is too premature to be considered antinatalism, or because it turns out that philosophy has not seriously challenged the question of procreation, or since the ideas mentioned in it are merely proto-antinatalism and not more, or because the promise of an old and rich history doesn’t live up to expectation, but exactly because it does. The history of the philosophical challenges to procreation is indeed ancient and many of them are quite impressive, and the ones taken from the New Testament and from Christian theology are also very surprising. Notwithstanding, it is all very saddening, since none of it made a significant practical impact.
There is something very depressing about the fact that philosophical challenges to procreation go so way back and are so culturally extensive, yet they haven’t infiltrated the public.

In the chapter devoted to Christianity there are many quotes that I found surprisingly sympathetic to antinatalistic ideas. However, the fact that many ideas in Christianity are sympathetic to antinatalistic ideas and yet de facto Christianity is a very pro-natalistic ideology, is a very strong indication for people’s desires and limitations. That is especially the case with the concept of hell which should have been, and still must be, a very strong antinatalistic argument yet it absolutely isn’t. However, since I have already addressed this issue in the former text, and since the book focuses more on Christian Scriptures and Christian theology than the concept of hell, I’ll not get in to it here. And as for christian texts, it doesn’t matter that much what is written in the Scriptures, the Gospels and theological books but what people practically see in them, and they usually see what they want or what is in their interests. For example, Jesus advocated for simplicity, humbleness, and peacefulness, but allegedly in his name people engaged in countless wars, and accumulated inapprehensible wealth. No religion is more capitalistic than Protestantism, and no religion is more ostentatious than Catholicism. People, as usual, interpreted things as they desire.

Even if early Christianity, that of the Gospels, had truly contained many antinatalist tendencies, it clearly evolved into an extremely pro-natalist ideology, with the Catholic Church officially forbidding the use of contraception and abortion. And one must be highly conspiracist to believe that such a radical shift was possible despite that people’s natural dispositions were compatible with these ideas. It is much more plausible that if anything, it is the ideas of early Christianity which didn’t quite suit people’s natural tendencies which are not exactly celibacy and asceticism, and the later ones were way more fitting, evidently, they have been extensively endorsed and remain up to this day.

People don’t need a religious propaganda about family and fertility, they have a built-in biological one. Long before Christianity emerged, humans have lived in a familial structure and were highly inclined to procreate. And except for some marginal extraordinary examples, that is basically cross cultural and from time immemorial. It is not as if before Christianity most humans throughout history have lived solitarily and abstinently, but exactly the opposite. Unfortunately humans are naturally very social and sexual animals. Celibacy, continence, chastity and barrenness are completely unnatural for humans. Familialist and fertilist religious propaganda is needless, it is literally preaching to the quire.

Since people naturally desire to procreate they stress the pro-natalistic aspects and conceal or ignore the antinatalistic ideas. They always do that when they are facing demands they find undesirable. Especially when they are asked to stop doing things they want to keep doing. For example, one of the most common ways they justify the consumption of animal products is that humans are animals and animals eat each other, thus it is natural for humans to eat animals. Even if for the sake of the argument we’ll accept that it is natural – and ignore the fact that none of the ways humans consume animals is natural, that none of the animals that humans are consuming are natural, that there is nothing natural about adult humans consuming the milk of another species (it is unprecedented in the natural world), and of course that even if it was natural it wouldn’t make it ethical since naturalness has nothing to do with goodness or rightness as something can be natural yet terrible (and the fact is that most of the natural things are indeed terrible) – humans are contradicting themselves when at the same time, often literally in the same conversion, they are also claiming that they are not at all animals or at least a special kind of species, a superior one and therefore deserve a special treatment and a special place on earth, and shouldn’t be treated  equality to animals. How does it settle? It doesn’t. And it doesn’t need to, since as conceptually wrong as speciesist humans are, practically they are right that they are a superior species, and a superior species doesn’t have to be conceptually right, rational and consistent as long as its mastery and power is not threatened, as long as it makes all the decisions anyway. People don’t do what is right and consistent but what is worthwhile and desirable… for them.

Obviously we can’t expect masses of people to stop procreating, let alone all together and entirely, because they have heard or read some philosophical fragments. But we can expect that societies won’t become so pro-natalist because its members have heard and read some philosophical fragments. Yet all societies did become pro-natalist. It is not that people were convinced by these philosophical fragments but didn’t stop breeding as a result of the need for helping hands, because their sexual desire overpowered their perceptions, and because during some eras among some societies it was a civic duty to produce new citizens, it is that they weren’t convinced. Otherwise as soon as people had alternatives they would have stopped breeding, otherwise births wouldn’t have been celebrated but treated as something that happen since people have sex and because people need working hands and because nations need soldiers. But people didn’t stop and births were always celebrated. Had some of these ancient ideas had some presence in some of people’s minds, on the practical level procreation probably would have only very slightly decreased before the contraception age, but on the theoretical level it should have been viewed entirely different a long time ago, and for the last two hundred years it should have been decreasing. None of that had happened.

It is probably a good place to clarify that I am not suggesting that the book implied that if people would realize how ancient and extensive the history of antinatalist ideas is, they would be convinced by them, or anything like that. It is a history book, surely one that was written by people with a very clear agenda, but it’s still a history book, not a book-length pamphlet aiming at convincing the readers that antinatalism’s antiquity origin is somehow evidence of its trueness. I am discussing such a claim while addressing the book not because it was made along it, but because that is one of the more probable practical implications to take from it.
And we can often observe such a move in relation to animal rights. Many activists and writers are pointing out that compassion towards animals is actually ancient, mainly by quoting all kinds of prominent historical figures, as well as mentioning that some of them such as Pythagoras, Plato, Plutarch, da Vinci, Newton, Voltaire, Ralph Waldo Emerson, Mary Shelley, Charlotte Bronte, Henry David Thoreau, Susan B. Anthony, Tolstoy, Kafka, Van Gogh, George Bernard Shaw, Gandhi, Albert Schweitzer and Albert Einstein were vegetarians. But it seems that they don’t realize how depressing it is that such a basic idea wonders around for so long yet is still so far from becoming the norm. And vegetarianism (not even veganism) is way more basic and easy than antinatalism.

The question of procreation may be seriously challenged since ancient times, but it had only started to be significantly challenged by the public in the late 60’s, and that is mainly by environmentalists concerned about overpopulation (some may go earlier for that matter to Thomas Malthus though I don’t know how effective his warnings were on the practical level). And as important as the environmental concern is in itself, and as important as the fear of world hunger is in itself, and both most certainly are, these are not philosophical challenges to procreation. They are obviously extremely important ethical questions but since they are ethically circumstantial and not fundamental, it is not really the same category. But obviously you are the last people who need to be reminded that overpopulation is very far philosophically from antinatalism, and even if one anyway counts it in, at least as part of challenging the question of procreation, as aforementioned, concerns about overpopulation definitely don’t have a long history but started to engage parts of the public only in the mid-seventies. And by some parts of the public I unfortunately mean very few people. Even nowadays, in the climate change era, most of the environmentalist groups don’t dare to suggest that people should have fewer children.

The only philosophical challenge of procreation that truly had a serious effect on the actual number of people who decided not to procreate is Liberalism, and its effect is indirect. The philosophical tradition of Liberalism which put the individual in the center of attention as opposed to the nation, society, god and etc., made people realize they don’t have to procreate if they don’t want to, because it is their desires that count most. And many people indeed decide not to procreate because they don’t want to. Nowadays, people don’t feel the same level of social and religious pressure to procreate as people felt just until a few decades ago, and some of these people feel that they don’t want to procreate because it might collide with other life choices they find more attractive than becoming parents, or that they don’t want to become parents because they find becoming parents undesirable. People have various options to manage their lives and some don’t include or might collide with being parents.

Having said that, pro-natalists social pressures are still very powerful, and most people still want to procreate, and not because of external pressures, but because of internal ones.

And anyway, Liberalism is not a philosophical challenge to the question of procreation, but a philosophical challenge to the question of choice, so in relation to procreation, it may challenge social pressure on people to procreate despite that they don’t want to, as well as challenging social pressure on people not to procreate despite they do want to (LGBT people, or ethnic minorities which are prevented from fertility treatments, ova donations, sperm donations and surrogacy, for example). So liberalism per se is most certainly not a philosophical challenge to the question of procreation, and in liberal societies, it is often the case that liberal notions are in fact a challenge to antinatalism.

More people in more areas of the world having more choices regarding procreation is obviously a very welcome social change as otherwise there would have been many more people in the world, and correspondingly many more victims. But that is not an evidence of the success of antinatalists ideas. The reproduction decrease in many areas of the world in the last couple of decades is not an evidence for antinatalists ideas finally starting to be implemented after a long history of them being merely theoretical, it is not due to late blooming of ancient antinatalists ideas, but mostly due to contemporary social, cultural and economic processes, and if philosophy had anything to do with it, it is the indirect effect of liberalism, not the direct effect of moralism.

The fact that most of the people who abstain from procreation are doing it because they don’t want to, and not because they think that ethically no one is allowed to, doesn’t really leave that much room for optimism. And the fact that both ideas: that one doesn’t have to procreate, and that one must not procreate; have a very very long history, yet both, even the child-free notion, are still relatively marginal; actually creates even more room for pessimism.
A long history of a philosophical idea doesn’t guarantee its implementation in the future.

Of course I am not suggesting that books about the history of ideas shouldn’t be written, they have a purpose and a benefit, however we must also consider their depressing aspect.
We must consider that the longer the history of very logical and basic ideas, the smaller their chances to become the norm. The fact that some ideas are out there for such a long time but were never picked up by the masses, can be an indication that as logical and basic as they may be, they are undesirable by the majority. Environmental ideas for example also have a very long history. And as opposed to antinatalism and antispeciesism, which I can understand why they are viewed as conceptually threatening to some people as both are anti-anthropocentric (on the face of it, it seems as if it is mostly antispeciesism but since antinatalism practically necessarily results in human extinction it is also an anti-anthropocentric view), protecting the environment is not necessarily anti-anthropocentric, it can be quite the opposite if it is presented as protecting the human race’s home (despite that it is only one species out of about 8.7 million other species). So environmentalism is not necessarily contradictive to anthropocentrism, and it is hard to think of other reasons why despite it being so basic and logical and historical, it is still such a marginal viewpoint.
And if you think that it is not really that marginal, as many people would agree that protecting the environment is important, surly much more than people who agree with antinatalism and antispeciesism, then consider that many people may also say that people have a right not to procreate and that animals have a right not to be tortured, but both are empty statements since to really agree with antinatalism is to not breed and to agree with antispeciesism is to not consume animal products, and in the same line of thought, considering how important and urgent environmental issues are, agreeing that protecting the environment is important is also an empty statement, as clearly the planet is under severe climate change and people know this for decades now, yet they still consume animal products despite their immense carbon footprint, they still use private cars on a daily basis, and many use airplanes occasionally, most don’t recycle, and of course, keep creating more people despite that it is the worst thing that a person can privately do in terms of climate change.
And that is because people are egocentric and most are also egoistic and very small minded. They are extremely concentrated on their small little lives here and now, therefore it is highly unlikely that the history of ideas would wake them up. But it should wake us up. It should wake the few people who do care, and who are not concentrated on their small little lives here and now, but on everyone’s lives, everywhere, at all times.

History books must make us realize that caring for others always has been and always will be a marginal position. Ethical ideas such as antinatalism would never prevail.

For me, the main practical function of a book such as History of Antinatalism, is as an alarm clock. We need to read this history book with an eye to the future. We must think that the worst thing that can happen is that the chapters about current antinatalism would become in the future additional chapters about the history of antinatalism, instead of being the last ones. We must think that this book should be the first and last history of antinatalism book, because another history of antinatalism book in the future means that antinatalism has failed, as for it to succeed there must be no future.

References

Kateřina Lochmanová et al. History of Antinatalism: How Philosophy Has Challenged the Question of Procreation (2020) ISBN 9798645624255

A Risk From Hell

I don’t believe in the existence of hell. And saving people from the option of eternal torture in hell was never part of my reasons to be an antinatalist. But it should be a reason to be an antinatalist for anyone who does believe in hell, as who would take the risk that their own children would endure eternal afterlife of torture?

The answer apparently is every person who believes in hell and nevertheless created people despite the risk of them ending up there (according to that person belief), and that’s probably tens of billions of people all along history.

People who believe that in the afterlife every human can either be destined to live in eternal bliss with God in heaven, or to be cast away from God’s presence and suffer eternally in hell, are not only putting their children’s lives at risk, but also their children’s afterlives, since they have no guarantee that their children will freely accept god and keep their faith for their entire lives, and therefore be salvaged. Salvation is not guaranteed for anyone and parents don’t know in advance whether their children would be redeemed by god or not, therefore they are taking a risk that their children would suffer eternal damnation. It is not just a double risk but an eternal one.

The fact that probably tens of billions of people along history took the risk that probably the same number of people would be eternally tortured in the worst way possible, goes to show how careless and selfish they are.

Probably the fact that almost all antinatalists don’t believe hell exists (except for the one we are living in right now), causes us not to be severely appalled by this notion, but tens of billions of people along history, and probably billions nowadays, genuinely believe that hell is an option and yet they are consciously exposing their own children to the risk of eternal life in the worst place they can imagine.

For many out of the probably tens of billions of people along history, not to procreate practically meant abstention from sex as many of them lived before they could have sex without the risk of creating new people that could end up in hell, but while unfortunately it is hard to expect people to abstain from sex because of the risk that their children would have a bad life on earth, it is absolutely plausible to expect that, or to find ways to minimize the risk of pregnancy because of the risk of your own children condemned to eternal hell! There is no greater risk than living the worst life imaginable, and forever. And even if you disagree that abstention is not too much to ask considering the risk of enteral hell for their own children, that expectation is relevant only for those who believe in hell and lived in times when their only sure and realistic option to avoid procreation (the option of abortion is ancient but it wasn’t available for most people during most of history) is to avoid sex (or at least sexual acts that can end up with impregnation). I don’t think I can estimate what the share of people who believed in hell after the contraception age is compared with people who believed in hell before the contraception age, but given the population growth curve, it is highly probable that despite that the concept of hell is very ancient, there were more procreations of people who believed in hell after the contraception age than before it. In any case it is billions of people, with many of them living among us, who according to their creeds are taking the risk that their own children would forever endure the worst things imaginable.

Because I am sure no one’s children are going to end up being tortured forever in hell, I am not bothered with the implications of that concept, and focus on things that could really happen to people’s children and that therefore they shouldn’t create them; but we should nevertheless be very bothered by the implications of the concept of hell.

First of all we must be bothered by the unbridgeable gaps antinatalists have with some people. We are so appalled by procreation, among other things because of all the horrible things that might happen in life on earth, and they are so enthusiastic about procreation despite all the horrible things that they believe might happen in the afterlife in hell, eternal life full of the worst things imaginable.

And secondly, we must consider the forces we are dealing with here.
It is not that as long as people believed in hell they have created less people, and once many of them stopped believing in hell they have created more people, but people have created new people all along history, and always regardless of the fate they believed is optional for them.
So, for many it is the option of eternal suffering in hell, for many others it is the high probability of lifelong suffering on earth due to a foreseen inborn disease, congenital anomaly, an abusive parent, living in a war zone, in a famine stricken area, extreme poverty, an inclination to various mental and physical health issues and etc., and for everyone it is the certainty of pain, sickness, fear, boredom, frustration, severe injuries, regret, broken-heartedness, loneliness, death, the fear of death and every other hardship life is full of.

Some of these harms are certain, some probable, some possible, and some may be merely imaginary. But the fact that even the worst option imaginable didn’t hinder the ones who seriously believe in it from procreating, must make us realize how strong people’s desire to procreate is, and how indifferent they are to the consequences of their decision to procreate. And therefore it is highly unlikely that our ethical and rational arguments could ever suffice.

Life on earth is so horrible in our view that we would have probably never felt the need to invent something such as hell as part of an antinatalist thought experiment. But for many people along history, and to this day, apparently, even if we would have used hell as an extremely exaggerated scenario in a thought experiment aiming to demonstrate the risk parents are exposing their children to when procreating, they wouldn’t be appalled, as according to them, it is an actual option.
The hell they are referring to, meaning eternal torture for nonbelievers, is imaginary. The real hell is the place where among many other horrors, many people believe in the imaginary version of it and yet they indifferently put their own children at risk of being tortured there forever.
The very existence of the imaginary hell must convince us to think of other ways to deal with the real one.

References

Kateřina Lochmanová et al. History of Antinatalism: How Philosophy Has Challenged the Question of Procreation (2020) ISBN 9798645624255

 

« Older posts Newer posts »